Difference between revisions of "Anarchy 43/Reflections on parents, teachers and schools"

From Anarchy
Jump to navigation Jump to search
imported>Ivanhoe
(Created page with "{{header | title = ANARCHY 43 (Vol 4 No 9) September 1964<br>Reflections on parents, teachers and schools | author = John Ellerby | section = | previou...")
 
imported>Ivanhoe
Line 33: Line 33:
 
{{aster}}
 
{{aster}}
  
 +
{{tab}}Histor&shy;ic&shy;ally, in this country, the strug&shy;gle to make edu&shy;ca&shy;tion free, com&shy;puls&shy;ory and uni&shy;versal, and out of the ex&shy;clus&shy;ive con&shy;trol of reli&shy;gious organ&shy;isa&shy;tions, was long and bitter, and the op&shy;po&shy;si&shy;tion to it came, not from liber&shy;tarian ob&shy;jectors, but from the up&shy;hold&shy;ers of priv&shy;ilege and dogma, and from those (both parents and em&shy;ploy&shy;ers) who had an eco&shy;nomic inter&shy;est in the labour of chil&shy;dren or a vested inter&shy;est in ignor&shy;ance. The very reason why it had to be made com&shy;puls&shy;ory ninety-<wbr>four {{p|277}}years ago was because chil&shy;dren were an eco&shy;nomic asset. Read&shy;ers of chap&shy;ters {{l|8|https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/ch08.htm}} and {{l|12|https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/ch12.htm}} of {{w|Marx|Karl_Marx}}{{s}} ''{{l|Capital|https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/index.htm}}'' will not dis&shy;sent from the as&shy;ser&shy;tion that the {{w|in&shy;dus&shy;trial re&shy;volu&shy;tion|Industrial_Revolution}} was made by the chil&shy;dren of the poor. As late as 1935 {{w|Lord Halifax|Edward_Wood,_1st_Earl_of_Halifax}}, as {{w|Pres&shy;id&shy;ent of the Board of Edu&shy;ca&shy;tion|Secretary_of_State_for_Education}}, op&shy;pos&shy;ing the pro&shy;posal to raise the school leaving age from four&shy;teen to fif&shy;teen, de&shy;clared that {{qq|public opinion would not toler&shy;ate an un&shy;con&shy;di&shy;tional raising of the age}} and the {{w|Bradford|Bradford}} tex&shy;tile manu&shy;fac&shy;turers as&shy;sured him that {{qq|there was work for little fingers there.}}
 +
 +
The no&shy;tion that primary ecu&shy;ca&shy;tion should be free, com&shy;puls&shy;ory and uni&shy;versal is very much older than the {{w|English Act of 1870|Elementary_Education_Act_1870}}. It grew up with the print&shy;ing press and the rise of prot&shy;est&shy;ant&shy;ism. The rich had been edu&shy;cated by the {{w|Church|Church_of_England}} and the sons of the rising bour&shy;geoisie in the {{w|grammar schools|Grammar_school#Early_grammar_schools}} of the Middle Ages. From the 16th century on arose a grad&shy;ual demand that all should be taught. {{w|Martin Luther|Martin_Luther}} ap&shy;pealed {{qq|To the Coun&shy;cil&shy;men of all Cities in {{w|Germany|Holy_Roman_Empire}} that they estab&shy;lish and main&shy;tain Christian Schools}}, ob&shy;serv&shy;ing that the train&shy;ing chil&shy;dren get at home {{qq|at&shy;tempts to make up wise through our ex&shy;peri&shy;ence}} a task for which life itself is too short, and which could be ac&shy;cel&shy;er&shy;ated by sys&shy;tema&shy;tic in&shy;struc&shy;tion by means of books. Com&shy;puls&shy;ory uni&shy;versal edu&shy;ca&shy;tion was founded in {{w|Calvin&shy;ist|Calvinism}} {{w|Geneva|History_of_Geneva#Reformation}} in 1536, and {{w|Calvin|John_Calvin}}{{s}} {{w|Scottish|Scotland}} dis&shy;ciple {{w|John Knox|John_Knox}} {{qq|planted a school as well as a {{w|kirk|Church_of_Scotland}} in every parish.}} In {{w|puritan Mas&shy;sachu&shy;setts|Massachusetts_Bay_Colony}} free com&shy;puls&shy;ory primary edu&shy;ca&shy;tion was intro&shy;duced in 1647. The common school, writes {{w|Lewis Mumford|Lewis_Mumford}} in ''{{l|The Condi&shy;tion of Man|https://archive.org/details/in.ernet.dli.2015.188937}}'':
 +
 +
<font size="2"><blockquote>{{tab}}&hellip; con&shy;trary to popular belief, is no be&shy;lated pro&shy;duct of 19th century demo&shy;cracy: I have pointed out that it played a neces&shy;sary part in the ab&shy;solu&shy;tist-<wbr>mech&shy;an&shy;ical form&shy;ula. {{w|Friedrich Wilhelm I|Frederick_William_I_of_Prussia}} of {{w|Prussia|Brandenburg-Prussia}}, fol&shy;lowing Luther{{s}} pre&shy;cept, made primary edu&shy;ca&shy;tion com&shy;puls&shy;ory in his realm in 1717, and foun&shy;ded 1,700 schools to meet the needs of the poor. Two ordin&shy;ances of {{w|Louis XIV|Louis_XIV_of_France}} in 1694 and 1698 and one of {{w|Louis XV|Louis_XV_of_France}} in 1724 re&shy;quired regular at&shy;tend&shy;ance at school. Even {{w|England|England}}, a strag&shy;gler in such mat&shy;ters, had hun&shy;dreds of private char&shy;ity schools, some of them foun&shy;ded by the {{w|So&shy;ci&shy;ety for Pro&shy;moting Chris&shy;tian Know&shy;ledge|Society_for_Promoting_Christian_Knowledge}}, which had been in&shy;cor&shy;por&shy;ated in 1699. {{w|Vergerious<!-- as spelt in original -->|Pier_Paolo_Vergerio}}, one of the earliest renais&shy;sance school&shy;masters, had thought edu&shy;ca&shy;tion an es&shy;sen&shy;tial func&shy;tion of the State; and cen&shy;tral&shy;ised au&shy;thor&shy;ity was now be&shy;lat&shy;edly taking up the work that had been neg&shy;lected with the wiping out of mu&shy;ni&shy;cipal free&shy;dom in the greater part of Europe.</blockquote></font>
 +
 +
{{tab}}All the ra&shy;tion&shy;al&shy;ist philo&shy;sophers of the 18th century thought about the prob&shy;lems of edu&shy;ca&shy;tion, and of them, the two acutest edu&shy;ca&shy;tional think&shy;ers ranged them&shy;selves on op&shy;pos&shy;ite sides on the ques&shy;tion of the ''organ&shy;isa&shy;tion'' of edu&shy;ca&shy;tion: {{w|Rousseau|Jean-Jacques_Rousseau}} for the State, {{w|Godwin|William_Godwin}} against it. Rousseau, whose ''{{w|Emile|http://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/5427}}'' pos&shy;tu&shy;lates a com&shy;pletely in&shy;di&shy;vidual edu&shy;ca&shy;tion (human so&shy;ciety is ig&shy;nored, the tutor{{s}} entire life is de&shy;voted to poor Emile), did never&shy;the&shy;less con&shy;cern himself with the so&shy;cial aspect, argu&shy;ing, in his ''{{l|Dis&shy;course on Polit&shy;ical Eco&shy;nomy|http://www.constitution.org/jjr/polecon.htm}}'' (1755)<!-- '(1758)' in original --> for public edu&shy;ca&shy;tion {{qq|under regu&shy;la&shy;tions pre&shy;scribed by the govern&shy;ment}}, for
 +
 +
<font size="2"><blockquote>{{tab}}If chil&shy;dren are brought up in com&shy;mon in the bosom of equal&shy;ity; if they are im&shy;bued with the laws of the State and the pre&shy;cepts of the General Will &hellip; we can&shy;not doubt that they will cher&shy;ish one another mu&shy;tually as broth&shy;ers &hellip; to become in time de&shy;fenders and fath&shy;ers of the country of which they will have been so long the chil&shy;dren.</blockquote></font>
 +
 +
{{p|278}}{{tab}}
 
</div>
 
</div>
  

Revision as of 17:33, 26 July 2017


275

Reflections on
parents, teachers
and schools

JOHN ELLERBY


What anarch­ists are after is per­sonal and so­cial auto­nomy—the idea that in­di­viduals and their organ­isa­tions should be self-reg­u­lat­ing auto­no­mous bodies. It is this which makes us ad­voc­ates of workers’ control in in­dus­try and which makes us en­thusi­astic about such ex­amples as we find of so­cial organ­isa­tions spring up from below, from people’s urge to sat­isfy their own needs, as op­posed to those which depend on a struc­ture of hier­archy, power and au­thor­ity in which one set of people give in­struc­tions and another set of people carry them out.

  The the­or­et­ical ap­pli­ca­tion of our ideas to the organ­isa­tion of edu­ca­tion is clear enough. The auto­nom­ous self-govern­ing school is the aim, and in view of the ob­vi­ous limits within which chil­dren may be said to govern them­selves, this means in prac­tice a school con­trolled by teach­ers by virtue of their func­tional re­spons­ibil­ity to chil­dren, and by parents because of their bio­lo­gical re­spons­ibil­ity for them. But the issue is more com­pli­ca­ted, for in both prim­it­ive and com­plex com­mun­it­ies it is recog­nised that all adults have a re­spons­ibil­ity towards chil­dren, which because of the vagar­ies and vicis­si­tudes of in­di­vidual parent­age, may have to be exer­cised on its behalf or on the child’s behalf. Once that is ad­mit­ted, we have of course ad­mit­ted that edu­ca­tion is the con­cern of the com­mun­ity. But what com­mun­ity? The state as in France, the local au­thor­ity as in the United States, or a mix­ture of the two as in Britain? And where does the re­spons­ibil­ity of the com­mun­ity begin and end?

  Should edu­ca­tion be com­puls­ory anyway? (And is the com­pul­sion to be ap­plied to the child or the parent?) Bakunin saw the ques­tion dia­lect­ic­ally:

  The prin­ciple of au­thor­ity, in the edu­ca­tion of chil­dren, con­sti­tutes the natural point of de­par­ture; it is leg­itim­ate, neces­sary, when ap­plied to chil­dren of a tender age, whose intel­li­gence has not yet openly de­veloped itself. But as the de­velop­ment of every­thing, and con­sequently of edu­ca­tion, im­plies the gradual nega­tion of the point of de­par­ture, this prin­ciple must dimin­ish as fast as edu­ca­tion and in­struc­tion ad­vance, giving place to in­creas­ing liberty. All ra­tional edu­ca­tion is at bottom nothing but this pro­gres­sive im­mola­tion of au­thor­ity for the benefit of liberty, the final ob­ject of edu­ca­tion neces­sarily
276

being the form­a­tion of free men full of re­spect and love for the liberty of others. There­fore the first day of the pupil’s life, if the school takes infants scarcely able as yet to stam­mer a few words, should be that of the great­est au­thor­ity and an almost entire ab­sence of liberty; but its last day should be that of the great­est liberty and the ab­solute aboli­tion of every vestige of the animal or divine prin­ciple of au­thor­ity.

  Eighty-five years later, Ethel Mannin in her utopian survey Bread and Roses took a more ab­solutely “liber­tarian” line:

  At this point you per­haps pro­test, “But if there is no com­pul­sion, what hap­pens if a child does not want to at­tend school of any kind, and the parents are not con­cerned to per­suade him?” It is quite simple. In that case the child does not at­tend any school. As he becomes adoles­cent he may wish to ac­quire some learn­ing. Or he may de­velop school-

going friends and wish to at­tend school because they do. But if he doesn’t he is never­the­less learn­ing all the time, his natural child’s creat­ive­ness work­ing in happy alli­ance with his free­dom. No Utopian parent would think of using that moral coer­cion we call ‘per­sua­sion’. By the time he reaches adoles­cence the child grows tired of run­ning wild, and begins to ident­ify himself with grown-

ups; he per­ceives the use­ful­ness of know­ing how to read and write and add, and there is prob­ably some special thing he wants to learn—

such as how to drive a train or build a bridge or a house. It is all very much simpler than our pro­fes­sional edu­ca­tion­ists would have us believe.

  Some of us think it is not that simple. But the point is aca­demic, for in prac­tice the deci­sion is that of the parents. Nowadays it is only highly soph­ist­ic­ated and edu­ca­ted people who bother to argue about whether or not it is desir­able that chil­dren should learn the three Rs. The law in this country does not in fact re­quire parents to send their chil­dren to school; it im­poses an obli­ga­tion on them to see that their chil­dren while within the com­puls­ory age, are re­ceiv­ing “an ap­propri­ate edu­ca­tion”. The oc­ca­sional pro­secu­tions of re­calcit­rant parents usually reveal a degree of apathy, in­dif­fer­ence or parental in­com­pet­ence that hardly pro­vides a good case for the op­ponents of com­pul­sion, though they do some­times rope in highly con­scien­tious parents whose views on edu­ca­tion do not hap­pen to co­incide with those of the local au­thor­ity. (Mrs. Joy Baker’s ac­count of her long and in the end suc­cess­ful struggle with the au­thor­it­ies will be re­viewed in a coming issue of anarchy). Usually, apart from a few of the rich, with their gover­nesses and tutors, there are not many parents with the time or skill to teach their chil­dren at home, and of those who could, many must feel it unfair to de­prive their chil­dren of the pleasures and so­cial ex­peri­ence of be­long­ing to a com­mun­ity of their peers, or may cherish the right of parents to have the kids out of their way for some of the time—and the recip­rocal right of their children to be outside the parental at­mo­sphere.

*   *   *
  Histor­ic­ally, in this country, the strug­gle to make edu­ca­tion free, com­puls­ory and uni­versal, and out of the ex­clus­ive con­trol of reli­gious organ­isa­tions, was long and bitter, and the op­po­si­tion to it came, not from liber­tarian ob­jectors, but from the up­hold­ers of priv­ilege and dogma, and from those (both parents and em­ploy­ers) who had an eco­nomic inter­est in the labour of chil­dren or a vested inter­est in ignor­ance. The very reason why it had to be made com­puls­ory ninety-four
277
years ago was because chil­dren were an eco­nomic asset. Read­ers of chap­ters 8 and 12 of Marx’s Capital will not dis­sent from the as­ser­tion that the in­dus­trial re­volu­tion was made by the chil­dren of the poor. As late as 1935 Lord Halifax, as Pres­id­ent of the Board of Edu­ca­tion, op­pos­ing the pro­posal to raise the school leaving age from four­teen to fif­teen, de­clared that “public opinion would not toler­ate an un­con­di­tional raising of the age” and the Bradford tex­tile manu­fac­turers as­sured him that “there was work for little fingers there.”

The no­tion that primary ecu­ca­tion should be free, com­puls­ory and uni­versal is very much older than the English Act of 1870. It grew up with the print­ing press and the rise of prot­est­ant­ism. The rich had been edu­cated by the Church and the sons of the rising bour­geoisie in the grammar schools of the Middle Ages. From the 16th century on arose a grad­ual demand that all should be taught. Martin Luther ap­pealed “To the Coun­cil­men of all Cities in Germany that they estab­lish and main­tain Christian Schools”, ob­serv­ing that the train­ing chil­dren get at home “at­tempts to make up wise through our ex­peri­ence” a task for which life itself is too short, and which could be ac­cel­er­ated by sys­tema­tic in­struc­tion by means of books. Com­puls­ory uni­versal edu­ca­tion was founded in Calvin­ist Geneva in 1536, and Calvin’s Scottish dis­ciple John Knox “planted a school as well as a kirk in every parish.” In puritan Mas­sachu­setts free com­puls­ory primary edu­ca­tion was intro­duced in 1647. The common school, writes Lewis Mumford in The Condi­tion of Man:

  … con­trary to popular belief, is no be­lated pro­duct of 19th century demo­cracy: I have pointed out that it played a neces­sary part in the ab­solu­tist-

mech­an­ical form­ula. Friedrich Wilhelm I of Prussia, fol­lowing Luther’s pre­cept, made primary edu­ca­tion com­puls­ory in his realm in 1717, and foun­ded 1,700 schools to meet the needs of the poor. Two ordin­ances of Louis XIV in 1694 and 1698 and one of Louis XV in 1724 re­quired regular at­tend­ance at school. Even England, a strag­gler in such mat­ters, had hun­dreds of private char­ity schools, some of them foun­ded by the So­ci­ety for Pro­moting Chris­tian Know­ledge, which had been in­cor­por­ated in 1699. Vergerious, one of the earliest renais­sance school­masters, had thought edu­ca­tion an es­sen­tial func­tion of the State; and cen­tral­ised au­thor­ity was now be­lat­edly taking up the work that had been neg­lected with the wiping out of mu­ni­cipal free­dom in the greater part of Europe.

  All the ra­tion­al­ist philo­sophers of the 18th century thought about the prob­lems of edu­ca­tion, and of them, the two acutest edu­ca­tional think­ers ranged them­selves on op­pos­ite sides on the ques­tion of the organ­isa­tion of edu­ca­tion: Rousseau for the State, Godwin against it. Rousseau, whose Emile pos­tu­lates a com­pletely in­di­vidual edu­ca­tion (human so­ciety is ig­nored, the tutor’s entire life is de­voted to poor Emile), did never­the­less con­cern himself with the so­cial aspect, argu­ing, in his Dis­course on Polit­ical Eco­nomy (1755) for public edu­ca­tion “under regu­la­tions pre­scribed by the govern­ment”, for

  If chil­dren are brought up in com­mon in the bosom of equal­ity; if they are im­bued with the laws of the State and the pre­cepts of the General Will … we can­not doubt that they will cher­ish one another mu­tually as broth­ers … to become in time de­fenders and fath­ers of the country of which they will have been so long the chil­dren.

278