Difference between revisions of "Anarchy 31/Anarchism and the cybernetics of self-organising systems"

From Anarchy
Jump to navigation Jump to search
imported>Ivanhoe
Line 18: Line 18:
 
{{p|s1}}<div style="text-align:justify;">{{sc|The intention of this article}} is to suggest that some of the con&shy;cepts used by {{w|cyber&shy;neti&shy;cians|Cybernetics}} study&shy;ing evolv&shy;ing self-<wbr>organ&shy;ising systems may be relev&shy;ant to anarch&shy;ist theory, and that some of the con&shy;clu&shy;sions drawn from this study tend to favour liber&shy;tarian models of social organ&shy;isa&shy;tion. Much of the spe&shy;cific&shy;ally cyber&shy;netic ma&shy;terial is drawn from lectures given by {{w|Gordon Pask|Gordon_Pask}} and {{w|Stafford Beer|Stafford_Beer}} at {{w|Salford College of Advanced Technology|University_of_Salford}}. They are not, of course, respons&shy;ible for any con&shy;clu&shy;sions drawn, except where expli&shy;citly stated.
 
{{p|s1}}<div style="text-align:justify;">{{sc|The intention of this article}} is to suggest that some of the con&shy;cepts used by {{w|cyber&shy;neti&shy;cians|Cybernetics}} study&shy;ing evolv&shy;ing self-<wbr>organ&shy;ising systems may be relev&shy;ant to anarch&shy;ist theory, and that some of the con&shy;clu&shy;sions drawn from this study tend to favour liber&shy;tarian models of social organ&shy;isa&shy;tion. Much of the spe&shy;cific&shy;ally cyber&shy;netic ma&shy;terial is drawn from lectures given by {{w|Gordon Pask|Gordon_Pask}} and {{w|Stafford Beer|Stafford_Beer}} at {{w|Salford College of Advanced Technology|University_of_Salford}}. They are not, of course, respons&shy;ible for any con&shy;clu&shy;sions drawn, except where expli&shy;citly stated.
  
{{tab}}Firstly, what do we mean by a self-<wbr>organ&shy;ising system? One defini&shy;tion is simply {{q|a system in which to ''order'' in&shy;creases as time passes}}, that is, in which the ratio of the ''variety'' ex&shy;hibited to the max&shy;imum possible variety de&shy;creases; variety being a measure of the com&shy;plex&shy;ity of the system as it appears to an ob&shy;server, the uncer&shy;tainty for the ob&shy;server regard&shy;ing its beha&shy;viour. A system with large variety will have a larger number of pos&shy;sible states than one with smaller variety. Thus such a system may start by ex&shy;hibit&shy;ing very varied beha&shy;viour, ''e.g.''<!-- 'e.g.' not in italics in original --> a large number of dif&shy;fer&shy;ent re&shy;sponses to a given stim&shy;ulus may appear equally likely, but over a period of time the heha&shy;viour becomes less erratic, more pre&shy;dict&shy;able{{dash}}fewer and fewer dis&shy;tinct re&shy;sponses to a given stim&shy;ulus are pos&shy;sible (or, better, have a sig&shy;nific&shy;antly high prob&shy;abil&shy;ity.)
+
{{tab}}Firstly, what do we mean by a self-<wbr>organ&shy;ising system? One defini&shy;tion is simply {{q|a system in which to ''order'' in&shy;creases as time passes}}, that is, in which the ratio of the ''{{w|variety|Variety_(cybernetics)}}'' ex&shy;hibited to the max&shy;imum possible variety de&shy;creases; variety being a measure of the com&shy;plex&shy;ity of the system as it appears to an ob&shy;server, the uncer&shy;tainty for the ob&shy;server regard&shy;ing its beha&shy;viour. A system with large variety will have a larger number of pos&shy;sible states than one with smaller variety. Thus such a system may start by ex&shy;hibit&shy;ing very varied beha&shy;viour, ''e.g.''<!-- 'e.g.' not in italics in original --> a large number of dif&shy;fer&shy;ent re&shy;sponses to a given stim&shy;ulus may appear equally likely, but over a period of time the heha&shy;viour becomes less erratic, more pre&shy;dict&shy;able{{dash}}fewer and fewer dis&shy;tinct re&shy;sponses to a given stim&shy;ulus are pos&shy;sible (or, better, have a sig&shy;nific&shy;antly high prob&shy;abil&shy;ity.)
  
{{tab}}This def&shy;ini&shy;tion is, however, in osme ways re&shy;strict&shy;ive. The best such a system can do is to reach some sort of op&shy;timum state and stay there. Also, if we regard the system as a control system at&shy;tempt&shy;ing to main&shy;tain stabil&shy;ity in a fluctu&shy;ating en&shy;viron&shy;ment, the types of dis&shy;turb&shy;ance with which it can deal are limited by the fixed max&shy;imum variety of the system. This point will be dealt with later. The essen&shy;tial thing is that unpre&shy;dict&shy;able dis&shy;turb&shy;ances are liable to prove too much for the system.
+
{{tab}}This def&shy;ini&shy;tion is, however, in osme ways re&shy;strict&shy;ive. The best such a system can do is to reach some sort of op&shy;timum state and stay there. Also, if we regard the system as a {{w|control system|Control_system}} at&shy;tempt&shy;ing to main&shy;tain stabil&shy;ity in a fluctu&shy;ating en&shy;viron&shy;ment, the types of dis&shy;turb&shy;ance with which it can deal are limited by the fixed max&shy;imum variety of the system. This point will be dealt with later. The essen&shy;tial thing is that unpre&shy;dict&shy;able dis&shy;turb&shy;ances are liable to prove too much for the system.
  
 
{{tab}}Such con&shy;sidera&shy;tions suggest that it would be more fruit&shy;ful to in&shy;corpor&shy;ate in the defini&shy;tion the idea that the max&shy;imum pos&shy;sible variety might also differ at dif&shy;fer&shy;ent times. Thus Pask re&shy;stricts the term to situa&shy;tions where the history of {{q|the system}} can best be repre&shy;sented as a series S₀ S₁ &hellip; S''ₙ''<!-- 'n' not subscript in original --> each term a system with fixed max&shy;imum variety, and each self-organising in the first sense. With this defini&shy;tion we are {{p|271}}able to deal with control systems of the type found in living organ&shy;isms. Indeed, with a few limited excep&shy;tions, bio&shy;logical and social organ&shy;isa&shy;tion are, up to now, the only fields in which such control systems can be found. Some of the excep&shy;tions, in the shape of ar&shy;tifi&shy;cially con&shy;structed systems, despite their crude and ele&shy;ment&shy;ary nature in com&shy;par&shy;ison with living organ&shy;isms, do however exhibit re&shy;mark&shy;ably ad&shy;vanced beha&shy;viour, at least in com&shy;par&shy;ison with con&shy;ven&shy;tional con&shy;trol&shy;lers.
 
{{tab}}Such con&shy;sidera&shy;tions suggest that it would be more fruit&shy;ful to in&shy;corpor&shy;ate in the defini&shy;tion the idea that the max&shy;imum pos&shy;sible variety might also differ at dif&shy;fer&shy;ent times. Thus Pask re&shy;stricts the term to situa&shy;tions where the history of {{q|the system}} can best be repre&shy;sented as a series S₀ S₁ &hellip; S''ₙ''<!-- 'n' not subscript in original --> each term a system with fixed max&shy;imum variety, and each self-organising in the first sense. With this defini&shy;tion we are {{p|271}}able to deal with control systems of the type found in living organ&shy;isms. Indeed, with a few limited excep&shy;tions, bio&shy;logical and social organ&shy;isa&shy;tion are, up to now, the only fields in which such control systems can be found. Some of the excep&shy;tions, in the shape of ar&shy;tifi&shy;cially con&shy;structed systems, despite their crude and ele&shy;ment&shy;ary nature in com&shy;par&shy;ison with living organ&shy;isms, do however exhibit re&shy;mark&shy;ably ad&shy;vanced beha&shy;viour, at least in com&shy;par&shy;ison with con&shy;ven&shy;tional con&shy;trol&shy;lers.
Line 70: Line 70:
 
{{tab}}Regard&shy;ing the group as a de&shy;cision maker, Pask sug&shy;gests that this is perhaps the only sense in which {{q|two heads are better than one}} is true{{dash}}if the {{q|two heads}} con&shy;sti&shy;tute a self-<wbr>organ&shy;ising system. The clue as to why a number of heads, ''e.g.'', notori&shy;ously, in com&shy;mit&shy;tees, often turn out to be much worse than one, is, he sug&shy;gests, this busi&shy;ness of role as&shy;sign&shy;ment and stereo&shy;typed pro&shy;ced&shy;ure. He has not, however, sug&shy;gested why this should arise.
 
{{tab}}Regard&shy;ing the group as a de&shy;cision maker, Pask sug&shy;gests that this is perhaps the only sense in which {{q|two heads are better than one}} is true{{dash}}if the {{q|two heads}} con&shy;sti&shy;tute a self-<wbr>organ&shy;ising system. The clue as to why a number of heads, ''e.g.'', notori&shy;ously, in com&shy;mit&shy;tees, often turn out to be much worse than one, is, he sug&shy;gests, this busi&shy;ness of role as&shy;sign&shy;ment and stereo&shy;typed pro&shy;ced&shy;ure. He has not, however, sug&shy;gested why this should arise.
  
{{tab}}Drawing on know&shy;ledge of beha&shy;viour of a self-<wbr>organ&shy;ising nature {{p|274}}ex&shy;hibited in other groups, ''e.g.'' in&shy;formal shop-<wbr>floor organ&shy;isa&shy;tion, the adapt&shy;abil&shy;ity and effi&shy;ciency ex&shy;hibited in in&shy;stances of col&shy;cect&shy;ive con&shy;tract working, and similar phe&shy;nomena,<ref>See, for example, the paper by {{w|Trist|Eric_Trist}} on col&shy;lect&shy;ive con&shy;tract working in the {{w|Durham|County_Durham}} coal&shy;field quoted by {{w|H. Clegg|Hugh_Clegg_(industrial_relations)}} in '''A New Ap&shy;proach to Indus&shy;trial Demo&shy;cracy''' (Black&shy;well 1960) and the dis&shy;cus&shy;sion of this book by [[Author:Geoffrey Ostergaard|Geoffrey Oster&shy;gaard]] in [[Anarchy 2/Approaches to industrial democracy|ANARCHY 2]]. Note the ap&shy;pear&shy;ance of new ele&shy;ments of job rota&shy;tion.<br>{{tab}}Despite his empha&shy;sis on the formal aspects of worker organ&shy;isa&shy;tion, {{w|Melman|Seymour_Melman}}{{s}} ana&shy;lysis (see Note 1) of the worker de&shy;cision pro&shy;cess at {{w|Standard{{s}}|Standard_Motor_Company}} brings out many of the carac&shy;ter&shy;istics of a self-<wbr>organ&shy;ising system: the evolving nature of the process; the diffi&shy;culty of de&shy;termin&shy;ing where a par&shy;tic&shy;ular de&shy;cision was made; chan&shy;ging domin&shy;ance; the way in which the cumul&shy;ative ex&shy;peri&shy;ence of the group changes the frame of refer&shy;ence against which subse&shy;quent prob&shy;lems are set for solu&shy;tion. A better idea of the gang system from which this derives can, however, be ob&shy;tained from [[Author:Reg Wright|Reg Wright]]{{s}} articles in [[Anarchy 2/The gang system in Coventry|ANARCHY 2]] & [[Anarchy 8/Erosion inside capitalism|8]].</ref> we may perhaps offer some sug&shy;ges&shy;tions as to how insti&shy;tu&shy;tional&shy;isa&shy;tion may arise in certain types of circum&shy;stances.
+
{{tab}}Drawing on know&shy;ledge of beha&shy;viour of a self-<wbr>organ&shy;ising nature {{p|274}}ex&shy;hibited in other groups, ''e.g.'' in&shy;formal shop-<wbr>floor organ&shy;isa&shy;tion, the adapt&shy;abil&shy;ity and effi&shy;ciency ex&shy;hibited in in&shy;stances of col&shy;lect&shy;ive con&shy;tract working, and similar phe&shy;nomena,<ref>See, for example, the paper by {{w|Trist|Eric_Trist}} on col&shy;lect&shy;ive con&shy;tract working in the {{w|Durham|County_Durham}} coal&shy;field quoted by {{w|H. Clegg|Hugh_Clegg_(industrial_relations)}} in '''A New Ap&shy;proach to Indus&shy;trial Demo&shy;cracy''' (Black&shy;well 1960) and the dis&shy;cus&shy;sion of this book by [[Author:Geoffrey Ostergaard|Geoffrey Oster&shy;gaard]] in [[Anarchy 2/Approaches to industrial democracy|ANARCHY 2]]. Note the ap&shy;pear&shy;ance of new ele&shy;ments of job rota&shy;tion.<br>{{tab}}Despite his empha&shy;sis on the formal aspects of worker organ&shy;isa&shy;tion, {{w|Melman|Seymour_Melman}}{{s}} ana&shy;lysis (see Note 1) of the worker de&shy;cision pro&shy;cess at {{w|Standard{{s}}|Standard_Motor_Company}} brings out many of the carac&shy;ter&shy;istics of a self-<wbr>organ&shy;ising system: the evolving nature of the process; the diffi&shy;culty of de&shy;termin&shy;ing where a par&shy;tic&shy;ular de&shy;cision was made; chan&shy;ging domin&shy;ance; the way in which the cumul&shy;ative ex&shy;peri&shy;ence of the group changes the frame of refer&shy;ence against which subse&shy;quent prob&shy;lems are set for solu&shy;tion. A better idea of the gang system from which this derives can, however, be ob&shy;tained from [[Author:Reg Wright|Reg Wright]]{{s}} articles in [[Anarchy 2/The gang system in Coventry|ANARCHY 2]] & [[Anarchy 8/Erosion inside capitalism|8]].</ref> we may perhaps offer some sug&shy;ges&shy;tions as to how insti&shy;tu&shy;tional&shy;isa&shy;tion may arise in certain types of circum&shy;stances.
  
 
{{tab}}Imagine a work&shy;shop of reason&shy;able size, in which a number of con&shy;nec&shy;ted pro&shy;cesses are going on, and where there is some vari&shy;ation in the factors af&shy;fact&shy;ing the work to be taken into ac&shy;count. There is con&shy;sider&shy;able evid&shy;ence that the workers in such a shop, working as a co-<wbr>oper&shy;ating group, are able to organ&shy;ise them&shy;selves without outside inter&shy;fer&shy;ence, in such a way as to cope effi&shy;ciently with the job, and show re&shy;mark&shy;able facil&shy;ity in coping with un&shy;fore&shy;see&shy;able diffi&shy;culties and disrup&shy;tions of normal pro&shy;cedure.
 
{{tab}}Imagine a work&shy;shop of reason&shy;able size, in which a number of con&shy;nec&shy;ted pro&shy;cesses are going on, and where there is some vari&shy;ation in the factors af&shy;fact&shy;ing the work to be taken into ac&shy;count. There is con&shy;sider&shy;able evid&shy;ence that the workers in such a shop, working as a co-<wbr>oper&shy;ating group, are able to organ&shy;ise them&shy;selves without outside inter&shy;fer&shy;ence, in such a way as to cope effi&shy;ciently with the job, and show re&shy;mark&shy;able facil&shy;ity in coping with un&shy;fore&shy;see&shy;able diffi&shy;culties and disrup&shy;tions of normal pro&shy;cedure.
Line 104: Line 104:
  
 
{{p|276}}{{tab}}I now wish to return from this ques&shy;tion of small group organ&shy;isa&shy;tion to that of larger systems, and con&shy;sider some criti&shy;cisms of con&shy;ven&shy;tional indus&shy;trial organ&shy;isa&shy;tion de&shy;veloped, in par&shy;tic&shy;ular, by Stafford Beer. He main&shy;tains that con&shy;ven&shy;tional ideas of control in complex situa&shy;tions, such as an indus&shy;trial company, or the economy of a country, are crude and inade&shy;quate. {{qq|The fact is,}} he says, {{qq|that our whole concept of control is naive, primit&shy;ive, and ridden with an almost retrib&shy;utive idea of caus&shy;al&shy;ity. Control to most people (and what a re&shy;flec&shy;tion this is upon a soph&shy;istic&shy;ated society!) is a crude process of coer&shy;cion.}}<ref>{{w|Beer|Stafford_Beer}} [[#cite_note-2|'''{{popup|op. cit.|opere citato: cited above}}''']] p.21.</ref>
 
{{p|276}}{{tab}}I now wish to return from this ques&shy;tion of small group organ&shy;isa&shy;tion to that of larger systems, and con&shy;sider some criti&shy;cisms of con&shy;ven&shy;tional indus&shy;trial organ&shy;isa&shy;tion de&shy;veloped, in par&shy;tic&shy;ular, by Stafford Beer. He main&shy;tains that con&shy;ven&shy;tional ideas of control in complex situa&shy;tions, such as an indus&shy;trial company, or the economy of a country, are crude and inade&shy;quate. {{qq|The fact is,}} he says, {{qq|that our whole concept of control is naive, primit&shy;ive, and ridden with an almost retrib&shy;utive idea of caus&shy;al&shy;ity. Control to most people (and what a re&shy;flec&shy;tion this is upon a soph&shy;istic&shy;ated society!) is a crude process of coer&shy;cion.}}<ref>{{w|Beer|Stafford_Beer}} [[#cite_note-2|'''{{popup|op. cit.|opere citato: cited above}}''']] p.21.</ref>
 +
 +
{{tab}}In the lecture re&shy;ferred to earlier, his main thesis was the im&shy;possi&shy;bil&shy;ity of truly effi&shy;cient control of a complex under&shy;taking by the type of rigid hier&shy;archic organ&shy;isa&shy;tion with which we are at present famil&shy;iar. That such systems manage to survive, and work in some sort of manner, as they obvi&shy;ously do, is, he sug&shy;gested, due to the fact that they are not en&shy;tirely what they are sup&shy;posed to be{{dash}}that there are un&shy;offi&shy;cial self-<wbr>organ&shy;ising systems and tend&shy;en&shy;cies in the organ&shy;isa&shy;tion which are essen&shy;tial to its sur&shy;vival.
 +
 +
{{tab}}Beer is un&shy;usu&shy;ally per&shy;cept&shy;ive, and frank, in em&shy;phas&shy;ising the preva&shy;lence and im&shy;port&shy;ance of un&shy;offi&shy;cial ini&shy;tiat&shy;ives at all levels, ''e.g.'' (of shop-<wbr>floor workers). {{qq|They arrange things which would horrify man&shy;age&shy;ment, if they ever found out}}, (of charge-<wbr>hands, etc.) {{qq|If ''they'' did not talk things over and come to mutual agree&shy;ments, the whole busi&shy;ness would col&shy;lapse.}}
 +
 +
{{tab}}The main key&shy;stones in Beer{{s}} argu&shy;ment are {{w|Ashby|W._Ross_Ashby}}{{s}} {{q|{{w|Prin&shy;ciple of Re&shy;quis&shy;ite Variety|Variety_(cybernetics)#The_Law_of_Requisite_Variety}}}} from the theory of homeo&shy;stasis, and in&shy;forma&shy;tion-<wbr>theor&shy;etic re&shy;quire&shy;ments for ade&shy;quate channel cap&shy;acity in a multi-<wbr>level system.
 +
 +
{{tab}}The prin&shy;ciple of re&shy;quis&shy;ite variety states that, if stabil&shy;ity is to be at&shy;tained, the variety of the con&shy;trol&shy;ling system must be at least as great as the variety of the system to be con&shy;trolled. We have already had an in&shy;stance of this, for this was really the trouble with our hypo&shy;thet&shy;ical com&shy;mit&shy;tee: due to its rigid struc&shy;ture and the need to issue in&shy;struc&shy;tions in terms of stand&shy;ard pro&shy;ced&shy;ures to be adopted, it could not pos&shy;sibly be effi&shy;cient in a situ&shy;ation of any com&shy;plex&shy;ity. If we made the further as&shy;sump&shy;tion that there was no organ&shy;isa&shy;tion of the work group other than that imposed by the com&shy;mit&shy;tee, chaos would be un&shy;avoid&shy;able. Ap&shy;proxi&shy;ma&shy;tions to this occur in {{q|{{w|working to rule|Work-to-rule}}}}. In normal working, the ini&shy;tiat&shy;ives of the shop-<wbr>floor workers would serve as an addi&shy;tional source of variety, this en&shy;abling the prin&shy;ciple of re&shy;quis&shy;ite variety to be satis&shy;fied, at least as far as normal vari&shy;ations in the factors af&shy;fect&shy;ing the pro&shy;duc&shy;tion situ&shy;ation were con&shy;cerned.
 +
 +
{{tab}}The relev&shy;ance of the re&shy;quire&shy;ments of channel cap&shy;acity is to the in&shy;ade&shy;quate, atten&shy;uated in&shy;forma&shy;tion avail&shy;able at the top of the hier&shy;archy{{dash|this is in&shy;evit&shy;able, for, in prac&shy;tice, the channel cap&shy;acity could never be made ade&shy;quate in the sort of pyr&shy;amidical struc&shy;tures we have}}and also to the in&shy;ade&shy;quacy of the formal channels be&shy;tween sub&shy;systems (''e.g.'' depart&shy;ments) which require to co-<wbr>ordin&shy;ate their activ&shy;ities.
 +
 +
{{tab}}To em&shy;phas&shy;ise how far con&shy;ven&shy;tional mana&shy;gerial ideas of organ&shy;isa&shy;tion are from satis&shy;fying the prin&shy;ciple of re&shy;quis&shy;ite variety, Beer used an {{p|277}}amusing parable con&shy;cern&shy;ing a Martian visitor to Earth, who exam&shy;ines the activ&shy;ities at the lower levels of some large under&shy;taking, the brains of the workers con&shy;cerned, and the organ&shy;isa&shy;tional chart pur&shy;port&shy;ing to show how the under&shy;taking is con&shy;trolled. The visitor is most im&shy;pressed, and deduces that the creatures at the top of the hier&shy;archy must have heads yards wide.
 +
 +
{{tab}}In dis&shy;cus&shy;sing the at&shy;tempts of an in&shy;ade&shy;quate control system to control a system of greater variety, Beer pointed to the accum&shy;ula&shy;tion of unas&shy;simil&shy;able in&shy;forma&shy;tion likely to occur as the control vainly strug&shy;gles to keep track of the situ&shy;ation.
 +
 +
{{tab}}A compar&shy;able con&shy;verse phe&shy;nomenon was pointed out by {{w|Proudhon|Pierre-Joseph_Proudhon}} in 1851, in what must rank as one of the most proph&shy;etic state&shy;ments about the de&shy;velop&shy;ment of social organ&shy;isa&shy;tion ever written: {{qq|(The gov&shy;ern&shy;ment) must make as many laws as it finds in&shy;terests, and, as in&shy;terests are in&shy;numer&shy;able, ''rela&shy;tions arising from one another mul&shy;tiply to infin&shy;ity,'' and ant&shy;agon&shy;ism is endless, law&shy;making must go on without stop&shy;ping. Laws, decrees, ordin&shy;ances, re&shy;solu&shy;tions, will fall like hail upon the un&shy;fortun&shy;ate people. After a time the polit&shy;ical ground will be covered by a layer of paper, which the geo&shy;logists will put down among the vicis&shy;situdes of the earth as the ''papyr&shy;aceous forma&shy;tion''.}}<ref>{{w|P.-J. Proudhon|Pierre-Joseph_Proudhon}}: '''{{l|The General Idea of the Revolu&shy;tion in the Nine&shy;teenth Century|http://fair-use.org/p-j-proudhon/general-idea-of-the-revolution/}}''' (Freedom Press, 1923).</ref> (The first italics are mine.)
 +
 +
{{tab}}This is also an early, and lucid, state&shy;ment of the com&shy;plex&shy;ity of the control situ&shy;ation in social organ&shy;isa&shy;tion.
 +
 +
{{tab}}Beer has some sug&shy;gest&shy;ive ideas on the ques&shy;tion of cent&shy;ral&shy;isa&shy;tion ''vs.'' de&shy;central&shy;isa&shy;tion in indus&shy;try. (That is, cent&shy;ral&shy;isa&shy;tion of control. The ques&shy;tion of cent&shy;ral&shy;isa&shy;tion of ''plant'' is a differ&shy;ent, if re&shy;lated, problem.) He puts the di&shy;lemma thus:
 +
 +
{{hang|Cent&shy;ral&shy;ise: in&shy;suffi&shy;cient channel cap&shy;acity, etc.{{dash}}cannot work effi&shy;ciently.}}
 +
 +
{{hang|De&shy;central&shy;ise: com&shy;pletely autonom&shy;ous units{{dash}}no cohe&shy;sion, prob&shy;ably ceases to be a system at all.<!-- no period in original -->}}
 +
 +
{{tab}}The point, he sug&shy;gests is that neither altern&shy;ative corres&shy;ponds to what we find in really effi&shy;cient systems, ''i.e.'' complex living organ&shy;isms. What we do find are a number of differ&shy;ent, inter&shy;locking control systems. Beer also draws atten&shy;tion to the pre&shy;val&shy;ence, and im&shy;port&shy;ance, of re&shy;dun&shy;dancy of poten&shy;tial com&shy;mand in self-<wbr>organ&shy;ising systems, and points out that it is com&shy;pletely alien to the sort of theory of organ&shy;isa&shy;tion found in indus&shy;try and in similar under&shy;takings.
 +
 +
{{tab}}The type of organ&shy;isa&shy;tion at which we should aim is, he sug&shy;gests, an organic one, in&shy;volving inter&shy;locking control systems, inter&shy;meshing at all levels, util&shy;ising the prin&shy;ciple of evolving self-<wbr>organ&shy;ising systems, with the channel cap&shy;acity and flow of in&shy;forma&shy;tion kept as high as pos&shy;sible.<ref>Compare also the con&shy;clud&shy;ing section of {{w|Pask|Gordon_Pask}}{{s}} '''An Ap&shy;proach to Cyber&shy;netics,''' in par&shy;ticu&shy;lar the dis&shy;cus&shy;sion of a {{q|bio&shy;logic&shy;ally organ&shy;ised}} factory.</ref>
 +
 +
{{tab}}He men&shy;tioned in this con&shy;nec&shy;tion an Amer&shy;ican busi&shy;ness&shy;man who claimed that his busi&shy;ness was, in part, organ&shy;ised along some&shy;what similar lines and seemed to work very well. The idea was that anybody at all, no matter how {{q|junior}} (I do not know whether this was actu&shy;ally re&shy;stric&shy;ted to what are termed {{q|staff}} or not), could call a con&shy;fer&shy;ence at short notice, to discuss any&shy;thing they wanted, whether con&shy;nected with {{p|278}}their work or not. Such a meeting could call in the pres&shy;ident of the company himself, or anyone they thought they needed.
  
  
 
-----
 
-----
  
<font size="2">{{note|aster|*}} {{q|best suited}} that is from the point of view of the group.
+
<font size="2">{{hang|{{note|aster|*}} {{q|best suited}} that is from the point of view of the group.}}
  
  
Line 117: Line 147:
 
{{DEFAULTSORT:Anarchism and the cybernetics of self organising systems}}
 
{{DEFAULTSORT:Anarchism and the cybernetics of self organising systems}}
 
[[Category:Anarchist philosophy]]
 
[[Category:Anarchist philosophy]]
 +
[[Category:Cybernetics]]
 +
[[Category:Labour and industry]]
 
[[Category:Articles]]
 
[[Category:Articles]]

Revision as of 16:07, 3 April 2017


270

Anarchism and the
cybernetics of self-organising
systems


s1
The intention of this article is to suggest that some of the con­cepts used by cyber­neti­cians study­ing evolv­ing self-organ­ising systems may be relev­ant to anarch­ist theory, and that some of the con­clu­sions drawn from this study tend to favour liber­tarian models of social organ­isa­tion. Much of the spe­cific­ally cyber­netic ma­terial is drawn from lectures given by Gordon Pask and Stafford Beer at Salford College of Advanced Technology. They are not, of course, respons­ible for any con­clu­sions drawn, except where expli­citly stated.

  Firstly, what do we mean by a self-organ­ising system? One defini­tion is simply ‘a system in which to order in­creases as time passes’, that is, in which the ratio of the variety ex­hibited to the max­imum possible variety de­creases; variety being a measure of the com­plex­ity of the system as it appears to an ob­server, the uncer­tainty for the ob­server regard­ing its beha­viour. A system with large variety will have a larger number of pos­sible states than one with smaller variety. Thus such a system may start by ex­hibit­ing very varied beha­viour, e.g. a large number of dif­fer­ent re­sponses to a given stim­ulus may appear equally likely, but over a period of time the heha­viour becomes less erratic, more pre­dict­able—fewer and fewer dis­tinct re­sponses to a given stim­ulus are pos­sible (or, better, have a sig­nific­antly high prob­abil­ity.)

  This def­ini­tion is, however, in osme ways re­strict­ive. The best such a system can do is to reach some sort of op­timum state and stay there. Also, if we regard the system as a control system at­tempt­ing to main­tain stabil­ity in a fluctu­ating en­viron­ment, the types of dis­turb­ance with which it can deal are limited by the fixed max­imum variety of the system. This point will be dealt with later. The essen­tial thing is that unpre­dict­able dis­turb­ances are liable to prove too much for the system.

  Such con­sidera­tions suggest that it would be more fruit­ful to in­corpor­ate in the defini­tion the idea that the max­imum pos­sible variety might also differ at dif­fer­ent times. Thus Pask re­stricts the term to situa­tions where the history of ‘the system’ can best be repre­sented as a series S₀ S₁ … S each term a system with fixed max­imum variety, and each self-organising in the first sense. With this defini­tion we are
271
able to deal with control systems of the type found in living organ­isms. Indeed, with a few limited excep­tions, bio­logical and social organ­isa­tion are, up to now, the only fields in which such control systems can be found. Some of the excep­tions, in the shape of ar­tifi­cially con­structed systems, despite their crude and ele­ment­ary nature in com­par­ison with living organ­isms, do however exhibit re­mark­ably ad­vanced beha­viour, at least in com­par­ison with con­ven­tional con­trol­lers.

  For an example of self-organ­ising beha­viour in this sense, we may con­sider a human being learn­ing to solve certain types of problem, as his beha­viour appears to an ob­server. Over an inter­val the beha­viour may appear self-organ­ising in the first sense. When, however, the learner adopts a new concept or method, there will be a dis­con­tinu­ity in the de­velop­ment of the beha­viour, after which it will again be self-organ­ising in the first sense, for a time, but now in­corpor­ating new pos­sibil­ities, and so on.

  In many dis­cus­sions of control situa­tions the concept of ‘Hier­archy’ appears very quickly. This may tend to make the anarch­ist recoil, but should not do so, since the usage is a tech­nical one and does not co­in­cide with the use of the term in anarch­ist criti­cisms of polit­ical organ­isa­tion.

  Firstly, the cyber­neti­cian makes a very import­ant dis­tinc­tion between two types of hier­archy, the ana­tom­ical and the func­tional, to use the termin­ology adopted by Pask. The former is the type exem­pli­fied in part by hier­arch­ical social organ­isa­tion in the normal sense (e.g. ‘tree of command’ struc­ture in in­dustry), that is: there are two (if two levels) actual dis­tin­guish­able con­crete entit­ies in­volved. The latter refers to the case where there may be only one entity, but there are two or more levels of in­forma­tion struc­ture opera­ting in the system—as for example in some types of neuron networks. A compar­able concept is Melman’s ‘dis­alien­ated de­cision pro­cedure’.[1] This idea might, I think, be sug­gest­ive to anarch­ists.

  Secondly, even in the case of ‘ana­tom­ical hier­archy’, the term only means that parts of the system can be dis­tin­guished dealing with dif­fer­ent levels of de­cision making and learning, e.g. some parts may deal dir­ectly with the en­viron­ment, while other parts relate to activ­ity of these first parts, or some parts learn about indi­vidual occur­rences, while others learn about se­quences of indi­vidual occur­rences, and others again about classes of se­quences.

  Even in the ana­tom­ical sense, then, the term need have none of the con­nota­tions of coer­cive sanc­tions in a ruler-ruled rela­tion­ship which are common in other usages.

  An im­port­ant phe­nomenon in self-organ­ising systems is inter­action between the in­forma­tion flowing in the system and the struc­ture of the system. In a complex system this leads to Redund­ancy of Poten­tial Com­mandit is impos­sible to pick out the crit­ical de­cision-making element, since this will change from one time to another, and depend on the in­forma­tion in the system. It will be evident that this implies that the idea of a hier­archy can have only limited ap­plica­tion in such a system.

272
  I will now attempt to give a brief sketch of a partly arti­ficial self-organ­ising system, in­volv­ing the inter­action be­tween human beings and a machine. This pro­vides ex­amples of the con­cepts intro­duced, and also, I feel, sug­gests import­ant general con­clu­sions about the char­acter­ist­ics of self-organ­ising groups—char­acter­ist­ics which may sound familiar to liber­tari­ans. The machine in ques­tion is a group teach­ing machine de­veloped by Gordon Pask.[2]

  Prior to this Pask had de­veloped indi­vidual teach­ing ma­chines which were import­ant ad­vances in the growth of applied cyber­netics.[3] However, on con­sider­ing the problem of group teach­ing (for skills where some calcul­able measure of the pupils’ per­form­ance, the rate of change of which will serve as a suit­able in­dica­tion of learn­ing, exists), he did not simply combine indi­vidual ma­chines.

  The import­ant insight he had was that a group of human beings in a learn­ing situ­ation, is itself an evolu­tion­ary system, which sug­gested the idea of the machine as a cata­lyst, modi­fy­ing the com­mun­ica­tion chan­nels in the group, and thus pro­ducing dif­fer­ent group struc­tures.

  In the de­velop­ment of the indi­vidual teach­ing ma­chines, the possi­bil­ity of the pupil domin­ating the ma­chine had already arisen. This Pask now ex­tended by intro­ducing the idea of a quality ‘money’ allo­cated to each member of the group, and used by each of them to ‘buy’ for himself control over the commun­ica­tion struc­ture of the group and over the partial spe­cifica­tion of the solu­tion pro­vided by the machine. Now, in the indi­vidual machine, the degree to which the pupil was helped was coupled to change of his degree of success. If he was becom­ing more success­ful then the help given was de­creased. In the group machine, the allo­cation of ‘money’ is coupled to two condi­tions—in­creas­ing success and in­creas­ing variety in the group struc­ture. This second condi­tion is the key to the novelty of the system.

  The system, then, has chan­ging domin­ance and ex­hibits redund­ancy of poten­tial com­mand.

  In practice, each pupil sits in a little cubicle pro­vided with buttons and indic­ators for com­mun­ica­tion, and a com­puter is used for control, calcul­ating the various meas­ures, etc. The oper­ator is pro­vided with some way of seeing what is going on, and can de­liber­ately make things dif­ficult for the group, by intro­ducing false in­forma­tion into the chan­nels, etc., seeing how the group copes with it.

  The prob­lems which Pask, at the time, had used in these group ex­peri­ments had been form­ulated as con­vey­ing in­forma­tion about the posi­tion of a point in some space, with noise in the com­mun­ica­tion chan­nels. The group had been asked to imagine that they are air traffic con­trol­lers, given co-ordin­ates spe­cify­ing the posi­tion of an air­craft at a certain time, for ex­ample.

  He sug­gests, however, that prob­lems of agree­ing on a choice of policy on a basis of agreed facts is not, in prin­ciple, very dif­fer­ent from the case in which ‘the facts’ are in dispute, and there is no ques­tion of adopt­ing any future policy—except of course the policy to adopt in order to ascer­tain the true facts and com­mun­icate them; this being the problem which the group solves for itself. It is in this sense that
273
the group may be re­garded as a de­cision maker.

  It will be noted that the state of the system when in equi­lib­rium is the solu­tion to the problem. Also that this solu­tion changes with time. This is also the case in the first example from purely human organ­isa­tion which oc­curred to me—a jazz band (an example also sug­gested by Pask).

  Pask em­phas­ised that he had not then had the op­portun­ity to obtain suffi­cient data to make any far-reach­ing well sub­stanti­ated gen­eral­isa­tions from these ex­peri­ments. The results he had ob­tained, however, were very inter­est­ing and, I think, give con­sider­able insight into the char­acter­istics of self-organ­ising systems, and their ad­vant­ages over other types of de­cision-makers.

  Some groups, after an initial stage while they were gaining famil­iar­ity with the machine, began as­sign­ing specific roles to their mem­bers and intro­ducing stand­ard pro­cedures. This led to a drop in effi­ciency and in­abil­ity to handle new factors intro­duced by spur­ious inform­ation, etc. The learn­ing curve rises, flat­tens, then drops sharply when­ever some new element is intro­duced. The system is now no longer self-organ­ising.

  Neces­sary charac­ter­istics for a group to con­sti­tuted self-organ­ising system, Pask sug­gests, are avoid­ance of fixed role-assign­ments and stereo­typed pro­ced­ures. This is of course tied up with re­dund­ancy of poten­tial com­mand.

  I think we might sum up ‘fixed role as­sign­ment and stereo­typed pro­ced­ures’ in one word—insti­tu­tional­isa­tion.

  Note that these char­acter­istics are neces­sary, not suffi­cientat the very least the group must first of all con­sti­tute a system in a mean­ing­ful sense; there must be com­mun­ica­tion be­tween the mem­bers, a suffi­cient struc­ture of in­forma­tion chan­nels and feed­back loops.

  The role of the com­puter in Pask’s system may be worry­ing some. Is his not an ana­logue of an author­itar­ian ‘guiding hand’? The answer is, I think, no. It must be re­membered that this is an arti­ficial exer­cise the group is per­form­ing. A problem is set by the oper­ator. There is there­fore no real situ­ation in actu­ality for the group to affect and observe the result of their efforts. It is this func­tion of de­termin­ing and feeding back success/failure in­forma­tion which the machine fulfils.

  The other im­port­ant aspect of the machine as a cata­lyst in the learn­ing process, we have already men­tioned. There is a rough analogy here with the role of ‘influ­ence leader’ in the Hausers’ sense,[4] rather than any author­it­arian ‘over­seer’. I will return to this ques­tion of the role of the machine shortly.

  Regard­ing the group as a de­cision maker, Pask sug­gests that this is perhaps the only sense in which ‘two heads are better than one’ is true—if the ‘two heads’ con­sti­tute a self-organ­ising system. The clue as to why a number of heads, e.g., notori­ously, in com­mit­tees, often turn out to be much worse than one, is, he sug­gests, this busi­ness of role as­sign­ment and stereo­typed pro­ced­ure. He has not, however, sug­gested why this should arise.

  Drawing on know­ledge of beha­viour of a self-organ­ising nature
274
ex­hibited in other groups, e.g. in­formal shop-floor organ­isa­tion, the adapt­abil­ity and effi­ciency ex­hibited in in­stances of col­lect­ive con­tract working, and similar phe­nomena,[5] we may perhaps offer some sug­ges­tions as to how insti­tu­tional­isa­tion may arise in certain types of circum­stances.

  Imagine a work­shop of reason­able size, in which a number of con­nec­ted pro­cesses are going on, and where there is some vari­ation in the factors af­fact­ing the work to be taken into ac­count. There is con­sider­able evid­ence that the workers in such a shop, working as a co-oper­ating group, are able to organ­ise them­selves without outside inter­fer­ence, in such a way as to cope effi­ciently with the job, and show re­mark­able facil­ity in coping with un­fore­see­able diffi­culties and disrup­tions of normal pro­cedure.

  There are two levels of task here:

  1. The complex of actual pro­duc­tion tasks.
  2. The task of solving the problem of how the group should be organ­ised to perform these first level tasks, and how in­forma­tion about them should be dealt with by the group.

  In situa­tions of the kind I am ima­gin­ing, the organ­isa­tion of the group is largely de­term­ined by the needs of the job, which are fairly obvious to all con­cerned. There is con­tinual feed-back of in­forma­tion from the job to the group. Any un­usual occur­rence will force itself on their notice and will be dealt with ac­cording to their re­sources at that time.

  Purely for the purpose of illus­tra­tion, let us now con­sider the situa­tion of the same type of shop, only this time as­suming that it is organ­ised by a com­mit­tee from outside the shop. The situa­tion in which the com­mit­tee finds itself is com­pletely dif­fer­ent from that of the work group. There are now three levels of problem:

  1. The prob­lems solved by the indi­vidual workers, i.e. their jobs.
  2. The problem of the organ­isa­tion of the work group.
  3. The problem of the organ­isa­tion of the com­mit­tee itself.

  The de­term­ining success/failure in­forma­tion for all these has still to come from (or at least is sup­posed to come from), the net result of the solu­tion of the first level prob­lems, i.e. the state of pro­duc­tion in the shop.

  The com­mit­tee is denied the con­tinu­ous feed-back which the group had. While working on its solu­tion to the second level problem, it will have no in­forma­tion about the success of its altern­atives, only previ­ous find­ings, coded, in prac­tice, in an inade­quate way. The degree of success will only be observ­able after a trial period after they have decided on a solu­tion. (Also un­usual cir­cum­stances can only be dealt with as types of occur­rence, since they cannot enumer­ate all pos­sibili­ties. This is import­ant in determ­ining the relat­ive effi­ciency of the two methods of organ­isa­tion, but is of less import­ance in our immedi­ate problem.)

275
  It follows that the com­mit­tee cannot solve the third problem by a method ana­logous to that used by the original work group in solving the second level problem; while working on the second level problem the com­mit­tee has no compar­able in­forma­tion avail­able to determ­ine the solu­tion of the third level problem. But they must adopt some pro­ced­ure, some organ­isa­tion at a given time. How then is it to be de­term­ined?

  In theory, such a con­trol­ler could still remain an adopt­ive self-organ­ising system, learn­ing the struc­ture to adopt in par­ticu­lar cir­cum­stances over a longer period of time, though it would still suffer from imper­fect in­forma­tion.

  In prac­tice, how­ever, the com­mit­tee promptly convene a meeting, assign spe­cific func­tions and decide on stand­ard pro­ced­ures. The actual de­term­ining in­forma­tion is prob­ably a mixture of person­ality factors (in­clud­ing ex­tern­ally de­prived status) and the exist­ing ideas on organ­isa­tion theory (in­clud­ing local pre­ced­ent) pos­sessed by the mem­bers. Once decided they will shelve the third level problem unless dis­aster, or a new su­perior, strikes, when a similar, but more cum­ber­some, pro­ced­ure will be neces­sary to re-organ­ise the com­mit­tee along the same general lines.

  In other words, within the cosed system of the com­mit­tee and work group, there is no, or virtu­ally no, coup­ling be­tween the success of the actual under­taking, i.e. the pro­duc­tion job, and the de­cision pro­ced­ure solving the third level problem. Worse, the factors influ­encing the solu­tion of this problem, far from in­creas­ing the pos­sible variety of the com­mit­tee, lead to rigid­ity and low variety. Owing to this struc­ture it will gener­ally prove less effi­cient than a single ima­gina­tive person.

  We might suggest, then, that it is this isola­tion from the process in terms of which the success of their own activ­ity is defined, which is gener­ally typical of the com­mit­tee situ­ation, which leads to their com­mon failure to exhibit self-organ­ising char­acter­istics, and fre­quent inade­quacy as de­cision makers.

  Con­sider the first case of the self-organ­ising work group again. Here it is the job itself which pro­vides the ana­logue of Pask’s machine, as far as feed­back of success/failure in­forma­tion is con­cerned. Also, it has fre­quently been pointed out that in a ‘face-to-face’ group in this kind of situ­ation (i.e. where the need for the situ­ation de­mand­ing col­lect­ive action are fairly obvious, and where some common cri­teria of success exist), that group lead­er­ship tends to be granted to the member or mem­bers best suited to the par­ticu­lar cir­cum­stances ob­tain­ing,* and to change as these circum­stances change. In other words, chan­ging domin­ance, de­term­ined by the needs of the situ­ation. Here again, the job, acting through the group psycho­logy of the face-to-face group per­forms a func­tion ana­logous to Pask’s machine, allo­cating tempor­ary domin­ance in ac­cord­ance with success.

276
  I now wish to return from this ques­tion of small group organ­isa­tion to that of larger systems, and con­sider some criti­cisms of con­ven­tional indus­trial organ­isa­tion de­veloped, in par­tic­ular, by Stafford Beer. He main­tains that con­ven­tional ideas of control in complex situa­tions, such as an indus­trial company, or the economy of a country, are crude and inade­quate. “The fact is,” he says, “that our whole concept of control is naive, primit­ive, and ridden with an almost retrib­utive idea of caus­al­ity. Control to most people (and what a re­flec­tion this is upon a soph­istic­ated society!) is a crude process of coer­cion.”[6]

  In the lecture re­ferred to earlier, his main thesis was the im­possi­bil­ity of truly effi­cient control of a complex under­taking by the type of rigid hier­archic organ­isa­tion with which we are at present famil­iar. That such systems manage to survive, and work in some sort of manner, as they obvi­ously do, is, he sug­gested, due to the fact that they are not en­tirely what they are sup­posed to be—that there are un­offi­cial self-organ­ising systems and tend­en­cies in the organ­isa­tion which are essen­tial to its sur­vival.

  Beer is un­usu­ally per­cept­ive, and frank, in em­phas­ising the preva­lence and im­port­ance of un­offi­cial ini­tiat­ives at all levels, e.g. (of shop-floor workers). “They arrange things which would horrify man­age­ment, if they ever found out”, (of charge-hands, etc.) “If they did not talk things over and come to mutual agree­ments, the whole busi­ness would col­lapse.”

  The main key­stones in Beer’s argu­ment are Ashby’s ‘Prin­ciple of Re­quis­ite Variety’ from the theory of homeo­stasis, and in­forma­tion-theor­etic re­quire­ments for ade­quate channel cap­acity in a multi-level system.

  The prin­ciple of re­quis­ite variety states that, if stabil­ity is to be at­tained, the variety of the con­trol­ling system must be at least as great as the variety of the system to be con­trolled. We have already had an in­stance of this, for this was really the trouble with our hypo­thet­ical com­mit­tee: due to its rigid struc­ture and the need to issue in­struc­tions in terms of stand­ard pro­ced­ures to be adopted, it could not pos­sibly be effi­cient in a situ­ation of any com­plex­ity. If we made the further as­sump­tion that there was no organ­isa­tion of the work group other than that imposed by the com­mit­tee, chaos would be un­avoid­able. Ap­proxi­ma­tions to this occur in ‘working to rule’. In normal working, the ini­tiat­ives of the shop-floor workers would serve as an addi­tional source of variety, this en­abling the prin­ciple of re­quis­ite variety to be satis­fied, at least as far as normal vari­ations in the factors af­fect­ing the pro­duc­tion situ­ation were con­cerned.

  The relev­ance of the re­quire­ments of channel cap­acity is to the in­ade­quate, atten­uated in­forma­tion avail­able at the top of the hier­archy—this is in­evit­able, for, in prac­tice, the channel cap­acity could never be made ade­quate in the sort of pyr­amidical struc­tures we have—and also to the in­ade­quacy of the formal channels be­tween sub­systems (e.g. depart­ments) which require to co-ordin­ate their activ­ities.

  To em­phas­ise how far con­ven­tional mana­gerial ideas of organ­isa­tion are from satis­fying the prin­ciple of re­quis­ite variety, Beer used an
277
amusing parable con­cern­ing a Martian visitor to Earth, who exam­ines the activ­ities at the lower levels of some large under­taking, the brains of the workers con­cerned, and the organ­isa­tional chart pur­port­ing to show how the under­taking is con­trolled. The visitor is most im­pressed, and deduces that the creatures at the top of the hier­archy must have heads yards wide.

  In dis­cus­sing the at­tempts of an in­ade­quate control system to control a system of greater variety, Beer pointed to the accum­ula­tion of unas­simil­able in­forma­tion likely to occur as the control vainly strug­gles to keep track of the situ­ation.

  A compar­able con­verse phe­nomenon was pointed out by Proudhon in 1851, in what must rank as one of the most proph­etic state­ments about the de­velop­ment of social organ­isa­tion ever written: “(The gov­ern­ment) must make as many laws as it finds in­terests, and, as in­terests are in­numer­able, rela­tions arising from one another mul­tiply to infin­ity, and ant­agon­ism is endless, law­making must go on without stop­ping. Laws, decrees, ordin­ances, re­solu­tions, will fall like hail upon the un­fortun­ate people. After a time the polit­ical ground will be covered by a layer of paper, which the geo­logists will put down among the vicis­situdes of the earth as the papyr­aceous forma­tion.”[7] (The first italics are mine.)

  This is also an early, and lucid, state­ment of the com­plex­ity of the control situ­ation in social organ­isa­tion.

  Beer has some sug­gest­ive ideas on the ques­tion of cent­ral­isa­tion vs. de­central­isa­tion in indus­try. (That is, cent­ral­isa­tion of control. The ques­tion of cent­ral­isa­tion of plant is a differ­ent, if re­lated, problem.) He puts the di­lemma thus:

Cent­ral­ise: in­suffi­cient channel cap­acity, etc.—cannot work effi­ciently.
De­central­ise: com­pletely autonom­ous units—no cohe­sion, prob­ably ceases to be a system at all.

  The point, he sug­gests is that neither altern­ative corres­ponds to what we find in really effi­cient systems, i.e. complex living organ­isms. What we do find are a number of differ­ent, inter­locking control systems. Beer also draws atten­tion to the pre­val­ence, and im­port­ance, of re­dun­dancy of poten­tial com­mand in self-organ­ising systems, and points out that it is com­pletely alien to the sort of theory of organ­isa­tion found in indus­try and in similar under­takings.

  The type of organ­isa­tion at which we should aim is, he sug­gests, an organic one, in­volving inter­locking control systems, inter­meshing at all levels, util­ising the prin­ciple of evolving self-organ­ising systems, with the channel cap­acity and flow of in­forma­tion kept as high as pos­sible.[8]

  He men­tioned in this con­nec­tion an Amer­ican busi­ness­man who claimed that his busi­ness was, in part, organ­ised along some­what similar lines and seemed to work very well. The idea was that anybody at all, no matter how ‘junior’ (I do not know whether this was actu­ally re­stric­ted to what are termed ‘staff’ or not), could call a con­fer­ence at short notice, to discuss any­thing they wanted, whether con­nected with
278
their work or not. Such a meeting could call in the pres­ident of the company himself, or anyone they thought they needed.



* ‘best suited’ that is from the point of view of the group.



  1. See Seymour Melman: Decision-Making and Productivity (Blackwell, 1958).
  2. Gordon Pask: “Inter­ac­tion between a Group of Sub­jects and an Adapt­ive Auto­maton to produce a Self-Organ­ising System for De­cision-Making” in the sym­posium Self-Organ­ising Systems, 1962, ed. Jovits, Jacobi and Goldstein (Spartan Books).
  3. See Stafford Beer: Cyber­netics and Manage­ment (English Uni­ver­sities Press, 1959) pp.123-127, and Gordon Pask: An Ap­proach to Cyber­netics (Hutchin­son 1961).
  4. See Richard and Heph­zibah Hauser: The Frat­ernal Society (Bodley Head, 1962).
  5. See, for example, the paper by Trist on col­lect­ive con­tract working in the Durham coal­field quoted by H. Clegg in A New Ap­proach to Indus­trial Demo­cracy (Black­well 1960) and the dis­cus­sion of this book by Geoffrey Oster­gaard in ANARCHY 2. Note the ap­pear­ance of new ele­ments of job rota­tion.
      Despite his empha­sis on the formal aspects of worker organ­isa­tion, Melman’s ana­lysis (see Note 1) of the worker de­cision pro­cess at Standard’s brings out many of the carac­ter­istics of a self-organ­ising system: the evolving nature of the process; the diffi­culty of de­termin­ing where a par­tic­ular de­cision was made; chan­ging domin­ance; the way in which the cumul­ative ex­peri­ence of the group changes the frame of refer­ence against which subse­quent prob­lems are set for solu­tion. A better idea of the gang system from which this derives can, however, be ob­tained from Reg Wright’s articles in ANARCHY 2 & 8.
  6. Beer op. cit. p.21.
  7. P.-J. Proudhon: The General Idea of the Revolu­tion in the Nine­teenth Century (Freedom Press, 1923).
  8. Compare also the con­clud­ing section of Pask’s An Ap­proach to Cyber­netics, in par­ticu­lar the dis­cus­sion of a ‘bio­logic­ally organ­ised’ factory.