Difference between revisions of "Anarchy 85/Meliorism—a reply"
imported>Ivanhoe |
|||
(One intermediate revision by the same user not shown) | |||
Line 13: | Line 13: | ||
− | <div style="max-width:500px; margin:auto; | + | <div style="max-width:500px; margin:auto;"><div style="text-align:justify;">{{p|83}}{{tab}}By {{qq|melio­rism}} I under­stand a certain kind of social acti­vity or beha­viour{{dash}}a kind of acti­vity which is dis­tin­guished from other kinds of acti­vity, not so much by any quality or style of the acti­vity itself, but by its having certain ends or aims. Melio­rist acti­vity is that acti­vity which has as its end, or is aimed at, some social im­prove­ment. This account of what melio­rism is agrees, I think, sub­stan­tial­ly with that of [[../Meliorism|Molnar{{s}}]]. |
− | {{tab}}It might, however, be queried by some liber­tari­ans. They would argue that melio­rist acti­vity has a certain style{{dash}}it in­volves a certain mode of beha­viour, it has a certain in­trin­sic cha­rac­ter. The adjec­tives {{qq|servile}}, {{qq|con­for­mist}}, {{qq|devious}}, etc., spring to mind as ways that liber­tari­ans | + | {{tab}}It might, however, be queried by some liber­tari­ans. They would argue that melio­rist acti­vity has a certain style{{dash}}it in­volves a certain mode of beha­viour, it has a certain in­trin­sic cha­rac­ter. The adjec­tives {{qq|servile}}, {{qq|con­for­mist}}, {{qq|devious}}, etc., spring to mind as ways that liber­tari­ans have cha­rac­ter­ised what they take to be the in­trin­sic cha­rac­ter of melio­rism. However, to define melio­rism as acti­vity carried out in this manner would be to beg the ques­tion against those who claim that one can achieve worth­while results in the social sphere without, as it were, sacri­fi­cing one{{s}} personal integ­rity in the process. And it does seem to be an empi­rical ques­tion which we should not pre-<wbr>judge whether or not melio­rism is always accom­pa­nied by a certain cha­rac­teris­tic style of beha­viour. It seems best, there­fore, to adopt as a star­ting point a general cha­rac­teri­sa­tion of melio­rism as that acti­vity direc­ted towards the end of social im­prove­ment. |
{{tab}}Liber­tari­ans have in the past been averse to taking part in melio­rist acti­vity; they have usually, though not always, been content to air their grie­van­ces without trying to remedy them. Molnar has argued for a sub­stan­tial modi­fica­tion of this atti­tude. He has based his posi­tion on an exa­mina­tion and criti­cism of certain argu­ments which he takes to be used as support for the liber­ta­rian atti­tude, and which he claims do not in fact support that atti­tude. | {{tab}}Liber­tari­ans have in the past been averse to taking part in melio­rist acti­vity; they have usually, though not always, been content to air their grie­van­ces without trying to remedy them. Molnar has argued for a sub­stan­tial modi­fica­tion of this atti­tude. He has based his posi­tion on an exa­mina­tion and criti­cism of certain argu­ments which he takes to be used as support for the liber­ta­rian atti­tude, and which he claims do not in fact support that atti­tude. | ||
Line 21: | Line 21: | ||
{{tab}}I agree with Molnar to this extent: ''if'' the liber­ta­rian oppo­si­tion to melio­rism is based on the argu­ments that he consi­ders, then that oppo­si­tion is not jus­ti­fied. To the extent that liber­tari­ans have defen­ded their anti-<wbr>melio­rism by resor­ting to these consi­dera­tions, then their defence has been an in­ade­quate one. But, against this, I want to argue that the liber­ta­rian aver­sion to melio­rism is based on consi­dera­tions which Molnar ignores, and that these are crucial for an under­stan­ding of the liber­ta­rian atti­tude. I will further suggest that these consi­dera­tions are basic to liber­tari­anism{{dash}}basic in the sense that if one were to reject them one would cease to be a liber­ta­rian. As a conse­quence of this, where Molnar sug­gests that liber­tari­anism and melio­rism{{dash|albeit of a res­trained and selec­tive kind}}are compa­tible, I will argue that they are incom­pa­tible. Where Molnar asks that we reject the general {{p|84}}ques­tion {{qq|What is wrong with melio­rism?}}, I think we should accept it, and try to answer it. | {{tab}}I agree with Molnar to this extent: ''if'' the liber­ta­rian oppo­si­tion to melio­rism is based on the argu­ments that he consi­ders, then that oppo­si­tion is not jus­ti­fied. To the extent that liber­tari­ans have defen­ded their anti-<wbr>melio­rism by resor­ting to these consi­dera­tions, then their defence has been an in­ade­quate one. But, against this, I want to argue that the liber­ta­rian aver­sion to melio­rism is based on consi­dera­tions which Molnar ignores, and that these are crucial for an under­stan­ding of the liber­ta­rian atti­tude. I will further suggest that these consi­dera­tions are basic to liber­tari­anism{{dash}}basic in the sense that if one were to reject them one would cease to be a liber­ta­rian. As a conse­quence of this, where Molnar sug­gests that liber­tari­anism and melio­rism{{dash|albeit of a res­trained and selec­tive kind}}are compa­tible, I will argue that they are incom­pa­tible. Where Molnar asks that we reject the general {{p|84}}ques­tion {{qq|What is wrong with melio­rism?}}, I think we should accept it, and try to answer it. | ||
− | {{tab}}This will involve going | + | {{tab}}This will involve going over some pretty fami­liar mate­rial. Still, it seems worth going over if just to give it a certain empha­sis which might be missed. It is also neces­sary because it seems that it is just this fami­liar mate­rial that Molnar has chosen to ignore. |
− | {{tab}}Liberta­rians, as we know, are anar­chists, though admit­ted­ly anar­chists of a rather strange | + | {{tab}}Liberta­rians, as we know, are anar­chists, though admit­ted­ly anar­chists of a rather strange breed. Before we get into those ele­ments in liber­ta­rian thin­king which dis­tin­guish them from other anar­chists, it will be as well to stress at least one element in liber­ta­rian thin­king which they share with clas­sical anar­chists. This is, of course, the enor­mous, perhaps inor­di­nate, stress on freedom{{dash}}freedom, that set of condi­tions in which human acti­vity can be carried on unhin­dered, and in which indi­vi­dual and group inte­rests can be ex­pressed without barrier. Toge­ther with this is the corre­la­tive oppo­si­tion to those forces and insti­tu­tions which limit that freedom. Whereas other poli­tical creeds have, either expli­citly or impli­citly, settled for a limited freedom, anar­chists and liber­tari­ans have held out in the name of complete freedom, and have main­tained, or tried to main­tain, an uncom­promi­sing atti­tude towards those forces that stand in the way of that freedom. |
{{tab}}It is because liber­tari­ans try to main­tain this posi­tion that they are anar­chists; if they ceased to hold this posi­tion they would cease to be anar­chists{{dash}}they would be ratbags of a diffe­rent kind. What I want to stress is that this atti­tude is basic to liber­tari­anism, and because it is an ''atti­tude'' it is not, as such, subject to argu­ment or proof. Liber­tari­ans just have this atti­tude: it is their star­ting point. It is not the con­clu­sion of an argu­ment, nor a ter­mi­nus arrived at from the consi­dera­tion of pre­mi­ses. | {{tab}}It is because liber­tari­ans try to main­tain this posi­tion that they are anar­chists; if they ceased to hold this posi­tion they would cease to be anar­chists{{dash}}they would be ratbags of a diffe­rent kind. What I want to stress is that this atti­tude is basic to liber­tari­anism, and because it is an ''atti­tude'' it is not, as such, subject to argu­ment or proof. Liber­tari­ans just have this atti­tude: it is their star­ting point. It is not the con­clu­sion of an argu­ment, nor a ter­mi­nus arrived at from the consi­dera­tion of pre­mi­ses. | ||
Line 37: | Line 37: | ||
{{tab}}Given all this, we can imme­di­ately see the oppo­si­tion or, perhaps better, the lack of contact between the melio­rist and the liber­ta­rian. Melio­rists and refor­mers are con­cerned with ''ends''{{dash}}their acti­vity is cal­cula­ted to achieve certain results. For the melio­rist, the style of the acti­vity, the manner in which it is carried out must, to some extent, be subor­di­nate to the ends that he hopes to achieve by that acti­vity. This is because melio­rist acti­vity is acti­vity direc­ted towards change or im­prove­ment, i.e., the end must govern to some, though perhaps only a limited extent, the means. If this is not the case, then the acti­vity is wrongly des­cribed as being melio­rist. Liber­tari­ans, on the other hand, are con­cerned with a certain kind of style of acti­vity, and the conse­quen­ces of this acti­vity are a subor­di­nate consi­dera­tion. It may be that some acti­vity under­taken by liber­tari­ans will have as a conse­quence some im­prove­ment of the social scene; it may also be the case that its conse­quence is some change that we would not regard as an im­prove­ment; much more likely, it will not have any impor­tant conse­quen­ces at all. But all these consi­dera­tions con­cer­ning the out­come of the acti­vity will be subor­di­nate to ques­tions con­cer­ning the cha­rac­ter of the acti­vity as such. It is this dif­fer­ence of empha­sis which sets the liber­ta­rian apart from the melio­rist{{dash}}even the {{qq|res­trained and selec­tive}} melio­rist. | {{tab}}Given all this, we can imme­di­ately see the oppo­si­tion or, perhaps better, the lack of contact between the melio­rist and the liber­ta­rian. Melio­rists and refor­mers are con­cerned with ''ends''{{dash}}their acti­vity is cal­cula­ted to achieve certain results. For the melio­rist, the style of the acti­vity, the manner in which it is carried out must, to some extent, be subor­di­nate to the ends that he hopes to achieve by that acti­vity. This is because melio­rist acti­vity is acti­vity direc­ted towards change or im­prove­ment, i.e., the end must govern to some, though perhaps only a limited extent, the means. If this is not the case, then the acti­vity is wrongly des­cribed as being melio­rist. Liber­tari­ans, on the other hand, are con­cerned with a certain kind of style of acti­vity, and the conse­quen­ces of this acti­vity are a subor­di­nate consi­dera­tion. It may be that some acti­vity under­taken by liber­tari­ans will have as a conse­quence some im­prove­ment of the social scene; it may also be the case that its conse­quence is some change that we would not regard as an im­prove­ment; much more likely, it will not have any impor­tant conse­quen­ces at all. But all these consi­dera­tions con­cer­ning the out­come of the acti­vity will be subor­di­nate to ques­tions con­cer­ning the cha­rac­ter of the acti­vity as such. It is this dif­fer­ence of empha­sis which sets the liber­ta­rian apart from the melio­rist{{dash}}even the {{qq|res­trained and selec­tive}} melio­rist. | ||
− | {{tab}}Molnar, in the course of his paper, consi­dered and rejec­ted certain views which might be held to but­tress an anti-<wbr>melio­rist stance. I have agreed that, as they stand, these consi­dera­tions do not support a general oppo­si­tion to melio­rism. However, in the light of what I have said so far, some at least can be refor­mula­ted so as to appear much more plau­sible, | + | {{tab}}Molnar, in the course of his paper, consi­dered and rejec­ted certain views which might be held to but­tress an anti-<wbr>melio­rist stance. I have agreed that, as they stand, these consi­dera­tions do not support a general oppo­si­tion to melio­rism. However, in the light of what I have said so far, some at least can be refor­mula­ted so as to appear much more plau­sible, not perhaps as argu­ments in their own right, {{p|86}}but as ad­juncts to the basic posi­tion. For example, Molnar, in my view quite cor­rect­ly, rejec­ted the thesis that melio­rism is inef­fec­tive. As a uni­ver­sal gene­rali­sa­tion this appears to be plainly false. But what is more plau­sible, and what, perhaps, is meant by many who have made this claim, is the view that liber­ta­rian acti­vity, if it is to be consi­dered melio­rist, will be seen as inef­fec­tive melio­rism. |
− | {{tab}}What I have in mind here is the liber­ta­rian reac­tion to the ill-<wbr>informed criti­cism of liber­tari­anism which runs: {{qq|What do you hope to achieve?}} The short answer to this, of course, {{qq|Nothing}}. Any a­chieve­ment would be an unex­pec­ted bonus. It is just a mistake to judge liber­ta­rian acti­vity by the same stan­dards as melio­rist acti­vity; the latter is to be judged by its effec­tive­ness, the former by other cri­teria en­tire­ly. The point here is that the | + | {{tab}}What I have in mind here is the liber­ta­rian reac­tion to the ill-<wbr>informed criti­cism of liber­tari­anism which runs: {{qq|What do you hope to achieve?}} The short answer to this is, of course, {{qq|Nothing}}. Any a­chieve­ment would be an unex­pec­ted bonus. It is just a mistake to judge liber­ta­rian acti­vity by the same stan­dards as melio­rist acti­vity; the latter is to be judged by its effec­tive­ness, the former by other cri­teria en­tire­ly. The point here is that the liber­ta­rian has no need to make the claim that all melio­rism is inef­fec­tive. All he wants to say is that liber­ta­rian acti­vity is inef­fec­tive. And this is un­doubt­edly true, just because liber­ta­rian acti­vity is not aimed at effects. |
− | {{tab}}Another of Molnar{{s}} criti­cisms was direc­ted at the view that, as a conse­quence of taking part in refor­mist acti­vity, the initial liberal aims of the refor­mer are always cor­rup­ted, and are re­placed by | + | {{tab}}Another of Molnar{{s}} criti­cisms was direc­ted at the view that, as a conse­quence of taking part in refor­mist acti­vity, the initial liberal aims of the refor­mer are always cor­rup­ted, and are re­placed by interest in autho­rity, power, and mani­pula­tion. In short, he {{qq|sells out}}. Now, consi­dered as an empi­rical thesis, this is most pro­bably false. At the very least, it needs a lot more evi­dence than has thus far been adduced. But once again it is a thesis which liber­tari­ans have no need to defend, for, given the liber­tari­an{{s}} over­ri­ding inte­rest in a certain sort of acti­vity for its own sake, and the refor­mer{{s}} inte­rest in acti­vity as a means to an end, then it follows that a liber­ta­rian cannot become a refor­mer without ceasing to be a liber­ta­rian. If ceasing to be a liber­ta­rian is taken to be a species of {{qq|selling out}} (and I under­stand that it is taken this way in the best circles), then the thesis {{qq|he who takes up reform, sells out}} is, when res­tric­ted to a certain class of people, {{popup|viz.|videlicet: that is}} liber­tari­ans, not a gene­rali­sa­tion backed by insuf­fi­cient evi­dence, but an ana­ly­tic truth. |
− | {{tab}}The liber­ta­rian posi­tion is not, as I have out­lined it, free from obscu­ri­ties and dif­ficul­ties. Ques­tions which reserve dis­cus­sion and clari­fica­tion include the notion of {{qq|doing some­thing for its own sake}}, as dis­tin­guished from {{qq|doing some­thing as a means to an end}}. An account of this would | + | {{tab}}The liber­ta­rian posi­tion is not, as I have out­lined it, free from obscu­ri­ties and dif­ficul­ties. Ques­tions which reserve dis­cus­sion and clari­fica­tion include the notion of {{qq|doing some­thing for its own sake}}, as dis­tin­guished from {{qq|doing some­thing as a means to an end}}. An account of this would have to be more complex than the rather ''simpliste'' dis­cus­sion con­tined in this paper. It might, I think, allow that a certin acti­vity, which is worth doing for its own sake and is in fact done for its own sake, might have ends, and inten­ded ends, of a certain sort. For example, the work of a crea­tive artist might have certain ends, e.g., earning a living, despite the fact that it is pri­mari­ly worth doing for its own sake. An­alo­gous­ly, liber­ta­rian acti­vity might also have certain ends, but these would be a subor­di­nate consi­dera­tion to that of the acti­vity con­ceived as an end in itself. |
{{tab}}Further prob­lems concern the cha­rac­teri­sa­tion of the style of liber­ta­rian acti­vity, and the range of acti­vity covered by the tenets that I have out­lined. These ques­tions deserve, and perhaps will get, more atten­tion than they have been given in this paper, or by liber­tari­ans {{p|87}}in the past. | {{tab}}Further prob­lems concern the cha­rac­teri­sa­tion of the style of liber­ta­rian acti­vity, and the range of acti­vity covered by the tenets that I have out­lined. These ques­tions deserve, and perhaps will get, more atten­tion than they have been given in this paper, or by liber­tari­ans {{p|87}}in the past. | ||
− | {{tab}}But these are ques­tions which I can only mention without further dis­cus­sion. They arise out of a posi­tion which is, I think, central to liber­ta­rian thin­king, and which Molnar has ignored. Because of this, his con­clu­sion{{dash|that liber­tari­ans should change their atti­tude to melio­rism}}has been | + | {{tab}}But these are ques­tions which I can only mention without further dis­cus­sion. They arise out of a posi­tion which is, I think, central to liber­ta­rian thin­king, and which Molnar has ignored. Because of this, his con­clu­sion{{dash|that liber­tari­ans should change their atti­tude to melio­rism}}has been insuf­fi­cient­ly argued for. I have been con­cerned to indi­cate what I take to be the basis of the liber­ta­rian oppo­si­tion to melio­rism; until that basis has been sub­jec­ted to con­clu­sive criti­cism, I see no reason to accept the thesis that the liber­ta­rian atti­tude stands in need of revi­sion. |
<font size="2"><references></font> | <font size="2"><references></font> |
Latest revision as of 12:22, 4 April 2017
Meliorism—
a reply
It might, however, be queried by some libertarians. They would argue that meliorist activity has a certain style—
Libertarians have in the past been averse to taking part in meliorist activity; they have usually, though not always, been content to air their grievances without trying to remedy them. Molnar has argued for a substantial modification of this attitude. He has based his position on an examination and criticism of certain arguments which he takes to be used as support for the libertarian attitude, and which he claims do not in fact support that attitude.
I agree with Molnar to this extent: if the libertarian opposition to meliorism is based on the arguments that he considers, then that opposition is not justified. To the extent that libertarians have defended their anti-This will involve going over some pretty familiar material. Still, it seems worth going over if just to give it a certain emphasis which might be missed. It is also necessary because it seems that it is just this familiar material that Molnar has chosen to ignore.
Libertarians, as we know, are anarchists, though admittedly anarchists of a rather strange breed. Before we get into those elements in libertarian thinking which distinguish them from other anarchists, it will be as well to stress at least one element in libertarian thinking which they share with classical anarchists. This is, of course, the enormous, perhaps inordinate, stress on freedom—
It is because libertarians try to maintain this position that they are anarchists; if they ceased to hold this position they would cease to be anarchists—
Given that libertarians qualify as anarchists because of this basic common ground, we can now point out how libertarians differ from most other anarchists, certainly from those in the classical tradition. Libertarians believe that the achievement of a society in which this ideal of freedom is realised is impossible; they believe that no amount of propaganda, education, or political struggle will bring about a society even remotely resembling the anarchist utopia. (I don’t want to consider questions as to how this belief is justified. I think it is justified, though I think that the justification is not quite as straightforward a matter as libertarians have tended to believe. But this is by the way.) The point is that it is this belief that distinguishes libertarians from other anarchists, just as it is the uncompromising attitude towards freedom that distinguishes libertarians and anarchists from other political creeds.
Years ago, Molnar himself pointed out (Libertarian No. I (1957), p. 12) that the classical anarchists were not just utopian dreamers, but that there was another strand in their thought. On occasion, they stressed the reality of the present and actual engagement with authority, of the immediate struggle for emancipation, rather than the far distant, perhaps illusory, utopia, which they conceived to be the outcome of that struggle. It was in this mood that Bakunin wrote: “to think of the future is criminal”. And it is this strain in anarchist thinking whichLibertarians are concerned with the content of their activity, i.e., its quality as such, and are not concerned with the ends that it may or may not achieve. Libertarians see certain sorts of action as expressive of their belief in freedom; being free is, in a sense, acting in a certain way. They are concerned with the activity, not for what it is hoped that it will bring about, but because they think that it is worth doing for its own sake. That is, I believe, the content, or an important part of the content, of the notion of permanent protest.
Of course, this does not apply, nor is it meant to apply, to all activity undertaken by libertarians. It does not, for instance, apply to that activity which is concerned just with the mundane task of living, e.g., drinking, eating, etc. But it certainly does apply to activity in the socio-
Given all this, we can immediately see the opposition or, perhaps better, the lack of contact between the meliorist and the libertarian. Meliorists and reformers are concerned with ends—
What I have in mind here is the libertarian reaction to the ill-
Another of Molnar’s criticisms was directed at the view that, as a consequence of taking part in reformist activity, the initial liberal aims of the reformer are always corrupted, and are replaced by interest in authority, power, and manipulation. In short, he “sells out”. Now, considered as an empirical thesis, this is most probably false. At the very least, it needs a lot more evidence than has thus far been adduced. But once again it is a thesis which libertarians have no need to defend, for, given the libertarian’s overriding interest in a certain sort of activity for its own sake, and the reformer’s interest in activity as a means to an end, then it follows that a libertarian cannot become a reformer without ceasing to be a libertarian. If ceasing to be a libertarian is taken to be a species of “selling out” (and I understand that it is taken this way in the best circles), then the thesis “he who takes up reform, sells out” is, when restricted to a certain class of people, viz. libertarians, not a generalisation backed by insufficient evidence, but an analytic truth.
The libertarian position is not, as I have outlined it, free from obscurities and difficulties. Questions which reserve discussion and clarification include the notion of “doing something for its own sake”, as distinguished from “doing something as a means to an end”. An account of this would have to be more complex than the rather simpliste discussion contined in this paper. It might, I think, allow that a certin activity, which is worth doing for its own sake and is in fact done for its own sake, might have ends, and intended ends, of a certain sort. For example, the work of a creative artist might have certain ends, e.g., earning a living, despite the fact that it is primarily worth doing for its own sake. Analogously, libertarian activity might also have certain ends, but these would be a subordinate consideration to that of the activity conceived as an end in itself.
Further problems concern the characterisation of the style of libertarian activity, and the range of activity covered by the tenets that I have outlined. These questions deserve, and perhaps will get, more attention than they have been given in this paper, or by libertarians But these are questions which I can only mention without further discussion. They arise out of a position which is, I think, central to libertarian thinking, and which Molnar has ignored. Because of this, his conclusion—
<references>