Difference between revisions of "Anarchy 85/Meliorism"

From Anarchy
Jump to navigation Jump to search
imported>Ivanhoe
Line 24: Line 24:
 
{{tab}}{{qq|I seem to be able to write only prac­ti­cally, inven­ting expe­di­ents. … My way of writing a book of social theory has been to invent com­munity plans. My psy­cho­logy is a manual of thera­peu­tic exer­cises. A liter­ary study is a manual of prac­tical criti­cism. A dis­cus­sion of human nature is a program of peda­gogi­cal and poli­tical reforms. This present book is no excep­tion. It is social criti­cism, but almost in­vari­ably (except in moments of indig­na­tion) I find that I know what I don{{t}} like only by con­trast with some con­crete pro­posal that makes more sense.}}
 
{{tab}}{{qq|I seem to be able to write only prac­ti­cally, inven­ting expe­di­ents. … My way of writing a book of social theory has been to invent com­munity plans. My psy­cho­logy is a manual of thera­peu­tic exer­cises. A liter­ary study is a manual of prac­tical criti­cism. A dis­cus­sion of human nature is a program of peda­gogi­cal and poli­tical reforms. This present book is no excep­tion. It is social criti­cism, but almost in­vari­ably (except in moments of indig­na­tion) I find that I know what I don{{t}} like only by con­trast with some con­crete pro­posal that makes more sense.}}
  
Goodman is not in the tradi­tion of 18th and 19th century refor­merso were ob­sessed with the idea of a Grand Plan to cure all ills of mankind at one stroke and forever. His thought is there­fore not to be com­pared to clas­sical anar­chism for he seems inter­ested solely in piece­meal reforms and changes. In modern American society thin­king men are faced with a moral di­lemma:
+
{{tab}}Goodman is not in the tradi­tion of 18th and 19th century refor­merso were ob­sessed with the idea of a Grand Plan to cure all ills of mankind at one stroke and forever. His thought is there­fore not to be com­pared to clas­sical anar­chism for he seems inter­ested solely in piece­meal reforms and changes. In modern American society thin­king men are faced with a moral di­lemma:
  
{{qq|It is only by the usual tech­nolo­gical and orga­nisa­tio­nal proce­dures {{p|77}}
+
{{tab}}{{qq|It is only by the usual tech­nolo­gical and orga­nisa­tio­nal proce­dures {{p|77}}that any­thing can be accom­plished. But with these proce­dures, and the motives and perso­nali­ties that belong to them, fresh ini­tia­tive is dis­cou­raged and funda­men­tal change is pre­ven­ted.}}
 +
 
 +
{{tab}}Goodman rejects the general vali&shy;dity of the premi&shy;ses from which this pes&shy;simis&shy;tic con&shy;clu&shy;sion is drawn. He believes that the short&shy;comings and defects of the society in which he lives are ''in part'' due not to the absence of better alter&shy;na&shy;tives but to an un&shy;wil&shy;ling&shy;ness seri&shy;ously to con&shy;sider and accept certain poli&shy;cies{{dash}}the poli&shy;cies to which he gives the friend&shy;ly-<wbr>ironic label {{qq|utopian}}. This un&shy;wil&shy;ling&shy;ness is itself not an alto&shy;gether un&shy;change&shy;able, rock-<wbr>hard social fact on Good&shy;man{{s}} view. Resis&shy;tance to novelty or to propo&shy;sals which are or seem radical and dis&shy;tur&shy;bing, can itself be studied and under&shy;stood, and some&shy;times over&shy;come. Goodman, conscious that all is not for the best in the best of all pos&shy;sible worlds, be&shy;lieves that {{qq|some&shy;thing can be done about it}}. He thinks that there exist means which, without being self-<wbr>defea&shy;ting, are apt to further modest but conse&shy;quen&shy;tial ends. He calls them {{qq|expe&shy;di&shy;ents}}, and reminds us of {{w|Goethe|Johann_Wolfgang_von_Goethe}}{{s}} objec&shy;tive: {{qq|just to live on a little}}. The con&shy;trast with {{w|Marxist|Marxism}}-{{w|historicist|Historicism}} beliefs in the impos&shy;sibi&shy;lity of reform within capi&shy;ta&shy;lism could hardly be more complete.
 +
 
 +
{{tab}}How do liber&shy;ta&shy;rians react to all this? Dif&shy;feren&shy;ces of inte&shy;rest between Goodman and liber&shy;ta&shy;rians are obvious enough. He is much more {{popup|catholic|wide-ranging}} in his inte&shy;rests that we are. He is con&shy;cerned with town and com&shy;mu&shy;nity plan&shy;ning, with the aes&shy;the&shy;tic quality of life and the sur&shy;rounds of acti&shy;vi&shy;ties; he is inte&shy;res&shy;ted in the tech&shy;no&shy;logy and admi&shy;nis&shy;tra&shy;tion of edu&shy;ca&shy;tion; in voca&shy;tio&shy;nal gui&shy;dance; in psy&shy;cho&shy;the&shy;rapy; in youth camps; and in many other things which to the liber&shy;tarian-<wbr>in-<wbr>the-<wbr>street are either so many un&shy;knowns or else hobbies to be pursued unof&shy;fi&shy;cial&shy;ly. Some of his pre&shy;occu&shy;pa&shy;tions are then ''{{popup|ab initio|from the start}}'' quite un&shy;like&shy;ly to arouse much enthu&shy;siasm in our quar&shy;ters. Never&shy;the&shy;less we should not over&shy;stress the dif&shy;feren&shy;ces. For Goodman is among other things an anti-<wbr>mili&shy;ta&shy;rist, a critic of super&shy;sti&shy;tious ide&shy;olo&shy;gies, an advo&shy;cate of sexual freedom and of freedom of ex&shy;pres&shy;sion. We do have a lot in common with what ani&shy;mates the man. In any case if this were less true, liber&shy;ta&shy;rians, in view of their social theory, would still have to accept and meet the chal&shy;lenge of defi&shy;ning their atti&shy;tude to a re&shy;for&shy;mer of the Goodman mould. We can hardly ignore him just because his inte&shy;rests differ from ours on so many points.
 +
 
 +
{{tab}}I envi&shy;sage the stan&shy;dard liber&shy;ta&shy;rian res&shy;ponse to Goodman as an ap&shy;plica&shy;tion to a parti&shy;cular case of our general doc&shy;trine of anti-<wbr>refor&shy;mism. Thus I expect most liber&shy;ta&shy;rians would be cri&shy;ti&shy;cal of Good&shy;man{{s}} style of thin&shy;king, his prag&shy;ma&shy;tism. And I do not mean here criti&shy;cism of his ex&shy;ces&shy;ses, his occa&shy;sio&shy;nal blun&shy;ders and over-<wbr>all super&shy;fici&shy;ality. I meen a deep-<wbr>seated aver&shy;sion. The reasons for this aver&shy;sion fall into three rough cate&shy;go&shy;ries. (1) There is the thought that melio&shy;rism is inef&shy;fec&shy;tive: it regu&shy;lar&shy;ly or cha&shy;rac&shy;teris&shy;ti&shy;cally fails of its {{p|78}}inten&shy;ded effects, espe&shy;cial&shy;ly when the inten&shy;ded effects are genu&shy;inely liberal. (2) In addi&shy;tion to inef&shy;fec&shy;tive&shy;ness and perhaps more impor&shy;tant than it, melio&shy;rism regu&shy;larly gene&shy;rates unin&shy;ten&shy;ded and unwan&shy;ted effects which blight the hope of refor&shy;mers to have achieved a net im&shy;prove&shy;ment in the world by their efforts. (3) Finally, the result of melio&shy;rism will be confu&shy;sion in the mind and beha&shy;viour of the refor&shy;mer: his ends, being in con&shy;flict, will fall into dis&shy;array, and it is pre&shy;dic&shy;table that in such an even&shy;tua&shy;lity he will let go of his liberal inten&shy;tions before letting go of his prac&shy;tical stri&shy;vings.
 +
 
 +
{{tab}}Let me con&shy;sider these points in turn (and not just with special refe&shy;rence to Goodman). My general line will be to suggest that these criti&shy;cisms are seve&shy;rally ''over&shy;stated'' and ''exag&shy;ge&shy;rated'', and that the anti-<wbr>melio&shy;rism to which they add up is there&shy;fore ''too indis&shy;crimi&shy;nate''.
 +
 
 +
{{tab}}In consi&shy;der&shy;ing the charge of inef&shy;fec&shy;tive&shy;ness (utopi&shy;anism in the un&shy;friend&shy;ly sense) we should dis&shy;tin&shy;guish the tech&shy;ni&shy;cal impos&shy;sibi&shy;lity of pro&shy;posed poli&shy;cies from their un&shy;suit&shy;abi&shy;lity to the audi&shy;ence. By tech&shy;nical impos&shy;sibi&shy;lity I mean that there are, at the time and place in ques&shy;tion, no phy&shy;si&shy;cal, tech&shy;nolo&shy;gical, or eco&shy;nomic means to the ends envi&shy;saged, nor are there any means to the means. Defects under the second heading include the fol&shy;low&shy;ing:
 +
 
 +
{{tab}}There is no (effec&shy;tive) audi&shy;ence, e.g. Domain oratory.
 +
 
 +
{{tab}}It is the wrong (irre&shy;le&shy;vant, impo&shy;tent) audi&shy;ence. Goodman himself pro&shy;vides the example: there is some&shy;thing dis&shy;tinct&shy;ly odd about propa&shy;ganda for civic and poli&shy;tical pro&shy;po&shy;sals being dis&shy;semi&shy;nated in lite&shy;rary jour&shy;nals.
 +
 
 +
{{tab}}There are reasons to believe that the Policy is not accep&shy;table to the (right) audi&shy;ence.
 +
 
 +
{{tab}}It would be patent&shy;ly absurd to argue that all pro&shy;po&shy;sals for reform are tech&shy;nical&shy;ly im&shy;pos&shy;sible. Most of them, at any rate most of those nowa&shy;days put forward by radi&shy;cals, dis&shy;sen&shy;ters, libe&shy;rals and demo&shy;cra&shy;tic socia&shy;lists in our times are not in this class. In any case there is no ratio&shy;nal way of judging the matter ''{{popup|a priori|without empirical evidence}}''. The pos&shy;sibi&shy;lity or impos&shy;sibi&shy;lity of pro&shy;po&shy;sals must be as&shy;ses&shy;sed as they came up, in the light of the situ&shy;ation to which they are meant to apply. Some&shy;what more guar&shy;dedly the same can be said about the unac&shy;cep&shy;tabi&shy;lity of meli&shy;orist pro&shy;po&shy;sals. Whether a policy is or is not ac&shy;cep&shy;table is some&shy;times a more or less open ques&shy;tion which can be set&shy;tled con&shy;clu&shy;sive&shy;ly only by putting the policy forward and seeing hte public reac&shy;tion. (Goodman implies this when he calls his utopian pro&shy;po&shy;sals {{qq|hypo&shy;the&shy;ses}}.) Pre&shy;scin&shy;ding from ques&shy;tions of un&shy;cer&shy;tain&shy;ty, there is a second point to be made here. Suppose a pro&shy;posal passes all reaso&shy;nable tests, other than accep&shy;tabi&shy;lity to the appro&shy;pri&shy;ate audi&shy;ence. Is advo&shy;cacy of such a policy un&shy;realis&shy;tic simply because it is not imme&shy;idate&shy;ly accep&shy;table to those con&shy;cerned? The answer is not always yes. If the policy in ques&shy;tion is not of the now-<wbr>or-<wbr>never type, if, that is, imme&shy;di&shy;ate accep&shy;tance and imple&shy;menta&shy;tion is not of its essence, then even if it is now unac&shy;cep&shy;table there may be some point to advo&shy;ca&shy;ting the policy despite oppo&shy;si&shy;tion or indif&shy;fe&shy;rence.
 +
 
 +
{{tab}}Through advoca&shy;ting the policy at a certain time, some analogy {{p|79}}to it, or some part of it, may become more proba&shy;ble than other&shy;wise, espe&shy;cial&shy;ly at some subse&shy;quent time. We know that many piece&shy;meal changes are the result of the cumu&shy;la&shy;tive impact of advo&shy;cacy (and other things) spread over a period. Nor is it neces&shy;sary that these effects of one{{s}} advo&shy;cacy should be exactly calcu&shy;lable.
  
  

Revision as of 11:27, 7 October 2016

76
“My contention is that one has to weigh
the special cir­cum­stan­ces of each case, and cannot safely guide one’s conduct by hard-and-fast rules which know nothing of the cir­cum­stan­ces or charac­ter of the people concerned. Surely the duty of man is not to do what he can’t, but to do the best he can; and I believe that, by adop­ting ab­stract rules never to do this or that, never to use force, or money, or support a Govern­ment, or go to war, and by encum­ber­ing our con­scien­ces with line upon line and precept upon precept, we become less likely to behave reason­ably and rightly than if we atten­ded more to those next steps, the wisdom of which can be tested in daily life …”
<span data-html="true" class="plainlinks" title="Wikipedia: aylmer maude">aylmer maude, in criticism of Leo Tolstoy.  


s1
Meliorism

GEORGE MOLNAR


This talk is a plea for a revi­sion of the re­ceived liber­ta­rian atti­tude to melio­rism. By melio­rism I under­stand at­tempts to remedy or reform speci­fic grie­vances or defects in a demo­cra­tic society. Some of what I have to say arose out of re­flec­ting on a book of essays by Paul Goodman[1] However this is not a paper on Goodman. I’ll refer to his views at the outset and also make exem­plary use of his work in some places. But my main interest is in pos­sible liber­ta­rian reac­tions to him, and beyond that, in the stan­dard liber­ta­rian atti­tude to melio­rism.

  Goodman calls himself a “utopian socio­lo­gist”, meaning of course to be iro­ni­cal. He is a self-confessed prag­ma­tist, strongly inter­ested in prac­tical goals and in getting things done. Al­though at heart he is a social critic, his avowed inten­tion is to combine des­truc­tive criti­cism with posi­tive pro­posals whose accep­tance would improve the object of criti­cism or even replace it alto­gether with some­thing better.

  “I seem to be able to write only prac­ti­cally, inven­ting expe­di­ents. … My way of writing a book of social theory has been to invent com­munity plans. My psy­cho­logy is a manual of thera­peu­tic exer­cises. A liter­ary study is a manual of prac­tical criti­cism. A dis­cus­sion of human nature is a program of peda­gogi­cal and poli­tical reforms. This present book is no excep­tion. It is social criti­cism, but almost in­vari­ably (except in moments of indig­na­tion) I find that I know what I don’t like only by con­trast with some con­crete pro­posal that makes more sense.”

  Goodman is not in the tradi­tion of 18th and 19th century refor­merso were ob­sessed with the idea of a Grand Plan to cure all ills of mankind at one stroke and forever. His thought is there­fore not to be com­pared to clas­sical anar­chism for he seems inter­ested solely in piece­meal reforms and changes. In modern American society thin­king men are faced with a moral di­lemma:

  “It is only by the usual tech­nolo­gical and orga­nisa­tio­nal proce­dures
77
that any­thing can be accom­plished. But with these proce­dures, and the motives and perso­nali­ties that belong to them, fresh ini­tia­tive is dis­cou­raged and funda­men­tal change is pre­ven­ted.”

  Goodman rejects the general vali­dity of the premi­ses from which this pes­simis­tic con­clu­sion is drawn. He believes that the short­comings and defects of the society in which he lives are in part due not to the absence of better alter­na­tives but to an un­wil­ling­ness seri­ously to con­sider and accept certain poli­cies—the poli­cies to which he gives the friend­ly-ironic label “utopian”. This un­wil­ling­ness is itself not an alto­gether un­change­able, rock-hard social fact on Good­man’s view. Resis­tance to novelty or to propo­sals which are or seem radical and dis­tur­bing, can itself be studied and under­stood, and some­times over­come. Goodman, conscious that all is not for the best in the best of all pos­sible worlds, be­lieves that “some­thing can be done about it”. He thinks that there exist means which, without being self-defea­ting, are apt to further modest but conse­quen­tial ends. He calls them “expe­di­ents”, and reminds us of Goethe’s objec­tive: “just to live on a little”. The con­trast with Marxist-historicist beliefs in the impos­sibi­lity of reform within capi­ta­lism could hardly be more complete.

  How do liber­ta­rians react to all this? Dif­feren­ces of inte­rest between Goodman and liber­ta­rians are obvious enough. He is much more catholic in his inte­rests that we are. He is con­cerned with town and com­mu­nity plan­ning, with the aes­the­tic quality of life and the sur­rounds of acti­vi­ties; he is inte­res­ted in the tech­no­logy and admi­nis­tra­tion of edu­ca­tion; in voca­tio­nal gui­dance; in psy­cho­the­rapy; in youth camps; and in many other things which to the liber­tarian-in-the-street are either so many un­knowns or else hobbies to be pursued unof­fi­cial­ly. Some of his pre­occu­pa­tions are then ab initio quite un­like­ly to arouse much enthu­siasm in our quar­ters. Never­the­less we should not over­stress the dif­feren­ces. For Goodman is among other things an anti-mili­ta­rist, a critic of super­sti­tious ide­olo­gies, an advo­cate of sexual freedom and of freedom of ex­pres­sion. We do have a lot in common with what ani­mates the man. In any case if this were less true, liber­ta­rians, in view of their social theory, would still have to accept and meet the chal­lenge of defi­ning their atti­tude to a re­for­mer of the Goodman mould. We can hardly ignore him just because his inte­rests differ from ours on so many points.

  I envi­sage the stan­dard liber­ta­rian res­ponse to Goodman as an ap­plica­tion to a parti­cular case of our general doc­trine of anti-refor­mism. Thus I expect most liber­ta­rians would be cri­ti­cal of Good­man’s style of thin­king, his prag­ma­tism. And I do not mean here criti­cism of his ex­ces­ses, his occa­sio­nal blun­ders and over-all super­fici­ality. I meen a deep-seated aver­sion. The reasons for this aver­sion fall into three rough cate­go­ries. (1) There is the thought that melio­rism is inef­fec­tive: it regu­lar­ly or cha­rac­teris­ti­cally fails of its
78
inten­ded effects, espe­cial­ly when the inten­ded effects are genu­inely liberal. (2) In addi­tion to inef­fec­tive­ness and perhaps more impor­tant than it, melio­rism regu­larly gene­rates unin­ten­ded and unwan­ted effects which blight the hope of refor­mers to have achieved a net im­prove­ment in the world by their efforts. (3) Finally, the result of melio­rism will be confu­sion in the mind and beha­viour of the refor­mer: his ends, being in con­flict, will fall into dis­array, and it is pre­dic­table that in such an even­tua­lity he will let go of his liberal inten­tions before letting go of his prac­tical stri­vings.

  Let me con­sider these points in turn (and not just with special refe­rence to Goodman). My general line will be to suggest that these criti­cisms are seve­rally over­stated and exag­ge­rated, and that the anti-melio­rism to which they add up is there­fore too indis­crimi­nate.

  In consi­der­ing the charge of inef­fec­tive­ness (utopi­anism in the un­friend­ly sense) we should dis­tin­guish the tech­ni­cal impos­sibi­lity of pro­posed poli­cies from their un­suit­abi­lity to the audi­ence. By tech­nical impos­sibi­lity I mean that there are, at the time and place in ques­tion, no phy­si­cal, tech­nolo­gical, or eco­nomic means to the ends envi­saged, nor are there any means to the means. Defects under the second heading include the fol­low­ing:

  There is no (effec­tive) audi­ence, e.g. Domain oratory.

  It is the wrong (irre­le­vant, impo­tent) audi­ence. Goodman himself pro­vides the example: there is some­thing dis­tinct­ly odd about propa­ganda for civic and poli­tical pro­po­sals being dis­semi­nated in lite­rary jour­nals.

  There are reasons to believe that the Policy is not accep­table to the (right) audi­ence.

  It would be patent­ly absurd to argue that all pro­po­sals for reform are tech­nical­ly im­pos­sible. Most of them, at any rate most of those nowa­days put forward by radi­cals, dis­sen­ters, libe­rals and demo­cra­tic socia­lists in our times are not in this class. In any case there is no ratio­nal way of judging the matter a priori. The pos­sibi­lity or impos­sibi­lity of pro­po­sals must be as­ses­sed as they came up, in the light of the situ­ation to which they are meant to apply. Some­what more guar­dedly the same can be said about the unac­cep­tabi­lity of meli­orist pro­po­sals. Whether a policy is or is not ac­cep­table is some­times a more or less open ques­tion which can be set­tled con­clu­sive­ly only by putting the policy forward and seeing hte public reac­tion. (Goodman implies this when he calls his utopian pro­po­sals “hypo­the­ses”.) Pre­scin­ding from ques­tions of un­cer­tain­ty, there is a second point to be made here. Suppose a pro­posal passes all reaso­nable tests, other than accep­tabi­lity to the appro­pri­ate audi­ence. Is advo­cacy of such a policy un­realis­tic simply because it is not imme­idate­ly accep­table to those con­cerned? The answer is not always yes. If the policy in ques­tion is not of the now-or-never type, if, that is, imme­di­ate accep­tance and imple­menta­tion is not of its essence, then even if it is now unac­cep­table there may be some point to advo­ca­ting the policy despite oppo­si­tion or indif­fe­rence.

  Through advoca­ting the policy at a certain time, some analogy
79
to it, or some part of it, may become more proba­ble than other­wise, espe­cial­ly at some subse­quent time. We know that many piece­meal changes are the result of the cumu­la­tive impact of advo­cacy (and other things) spread over a period. Nor is it neces­sary that these effects of one’s advo­cacy should be exactly calcu­lable.


<references>

  1. Paul Goodman: Utopian Essays and Practical Proposals. Vintage Books, N.Y., 1964.