Difference between revisions of "Anarchy 43/Reflections on parents, teachers and schools"
imported>Ivanhoe (Created page with "{{header | title = ANARCHY 43 (Vol 4 No 9) September 1964<br>Reflections on parents, teachers and schools | author = John Ellerby | section = | previou...") |
imported>Ivanhoe |
||
Line 33: | Line 33: | ||
{{aster}} | {{aster}} | ||
+ | {{tab}}Histor­ic­ally, in this country, the strug­gle to make edu­ca­tion free, com­puls­ory and uni­versal, and out of the ex­clus­ive con­trol of reli­gious organ­isa­tions, was long and bitter, and the op­po­si­tion to it came, not from liber­tarian ob­jectors, but from the up­hold­ers of priv­ilege and dogma, and from those (both parents and em­ploy­ers) who had an eco­nomic inter­est in the labour of chil­dren or a vested inter­est in ignor­ance. The very reason why it had to be made com­puls­ory ninety-<wbr>four {{p|277}}years ago was because chil­dren were an eco­nomic asset. Read­ers of chap­ters {{l|8|https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/ch08.htm}} and {{l|12|https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/ch12.htm}} of {{w|Marx|Karl_Marx}}{{s}} ''{{l|Capital|https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/index.htm}}'' will not dis­sent from the as­ser­tion that the {{w|in­dus­trial re­volu­tion|Industrial_Revolution}} was made by the chil­dren of the poor. As late as 1935 {{w|Lord Halifax|Edward_Wood,_1st_Earl_of_Halifax}}, as {{w|Pres­id­ent of the Board of Edu­ca­tion|Secretary_of_State_for_Education}}, op­pos­ing the pro­posal to raise the school leaving age from four­teen to fif­teen, de­clared that {{qq|public opinion would not toler­ate an un­con­di­tional raising of the age}} and the {{w|Bradford|Bradford}} tex­tile manu­fac­turers as­sured him that {{qq|there was work for little fingers there.}} | ||
+ | |||
+ | The no­tion that primary ecu­ca­tion should be free, com­puls­ory and uni­versal is very much older than the {{w|English Act of 1870|Elementary_Education_Act_1870}}. It grew up with the print­ing press and the rise of prot­est­ant­ism. The rich had been edu­cated by the {{w|Church|Church_of_England}} and the sons of the rising bour­geoisie in the {{w|grammar schools|Grammar_school#Early_grammar_schools}} of the Middle Ages. From the 16th century on arose a grad­ual demand that all should be taught. {{w|Martin Luther|Martin_Luther}} ap­pealed {{qq|To the Coun­cil­men of all Cities in {{w|Germany|Holy_Roman_Empire}} that they estab­lish and main­tain Christian Schools}}, ob­serv­ing that the train­ing chil­dren get at home {{qq|at­tempts to make up wise through our ex­peri­ence}} a task for which life itself is too short, and which could be ac­cel­er­ated by sys­tema­tic in­struc­tion by means of books. Com­puls­ory uni­versal edu­ca­tion was founded in {{w|Calvin­ist|Calvinism}} {{w|Geneva|History_of_Geneva#Reformation}} in 1536, and {{w|Calvin|John_Calvin}}{{s}} {{w|Scottish|Scotland}} dis­ciple {{w|John Knox|John_Knox}} {{qq|planted a school as well as a {{w|kirk|Church_of_Scotland}} in every parish.}} In {{w|puritan Mas­sachu­setts|Massachusetts_Bay_Colony}} free com­puls­ory primary edu­ca­tion was intro­duced in 1647. The common school, writes {{w|Lewis Mumford|Lewis_Mumford}} in ''{{l|The Condi­tion of Man|https://archive.org/details/in.ernet.dli.2015.188937}}'': | ||
+ | |||
+ | <font size="2"><blockquote>{{tab}}… con­trary to popular belief, is no be­lated pro­duct of 19th century demo­cracy: I have pointed out that it played a neces­sary part in the ab­solu­tist-<wbr>mech­an­ical form­ula. {{w|Friedrich Wilhelm I|Frederick_William_I_of_Prussia}} of {{w|Prussia|Brandenburg-Prussia}}, fol­lowing Luther{{s}} pre­cept, made primary edu­ca­tion com­puls­ory in his realm in 1717, and foun­ded 1,700 schools to meet the needs of the poor. Two ordin­ances of {{w|Louis XIV|Louis_XIV_of_France}} in 1694 and 1698 and one of {{w|Louis XV|Louis_XV_of_France}} in 1724 re­quired regular at­tend­ance at school. Even {{w|England|England}}, a strag­gler in such mat­ters, had hun­dreds of private char­ity schools, some of them foun­ded by the {{w|So­ci­ety for Pro­moting Chris­tian Know­ledge|Society_for_Promoting_Christian_Knowledge}}, which had been in­cor­por­ated in 1699. {{w|Vergerious<!-- as spelt in original -->|Pier_Paolo_Vergerio}}, one of the earliest renais­sance school­masters, had thought edu­ca­tion an es­sen­tial func­tion of the State; and cen­tral­ised au­thor­ity was now be­lat­edly taking up the work that had been neg­lected with the wiping out of mu­ni­cipal free­dom in the greater part of Europe.</blockquote></font> | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{tab}}All the ra­tion­al­ist philo­sophers of the 18th century thought about the prob­lems of edu­ca­tion, and of them, the two acutest edu­ca­tional think­ers ranged them­selves on op­pos­ite sides on the ques­tion of the ''organ­isa­tion'' of edu­ca­tion: {{w|Rousseau|Jean-Jacques_Rousseau}} for the State, {{w|Godwin|William_Godwin}} against it. Rousseau, whose ''{{w|Emile|http://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/5427}}'' pos­tu­lates a com­pletely in­di­vidual edu­ca­tion (human so­ciety is ig­nored, the tutor{{s}} entire life is de­voted to poor Emile), did never­the­less con­cern himself with the so­cial aspect, argu­ing, in his ''{{l|Dis­course on Polit­ical Eco­nomy|http://www.constitution.org/jjr/polecon.htm}}'' (1755)<!-- '(1758)' in original --> for public edu­ca­tion {{qq|under regu­la­tions pre­scribed by the govern­ment}}, for | ||
+ | |||
+ | <font size="2"><blockquote>{{tab}}If chil­dren are brought up in com­mon in the bosom of equal­ity; if they are im­bued with the laws of the State and the pre­cepts of the General Will … we can­not doubt that they will cher­ish one another mu­tually as broth­ers … to become in time de­fenders and fath­ers of the country of which they will have been so long the chil­dren.</blockquote></font> | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{p|278}}{{tab}} | ||
</div> | </div> | ||
Revision as of 16:33, 26 July 2017
Reflections on
parents, teachers
and schools
The theoretical application of our ideas to the organisation of education is clear enough. The autonomous self-
Should education be compulsory anyway? (And is the compulsion to be applied to the child or the parent?) Bakunin saw the question dialectically:
The principle of authority, in the education of children, constitutes the natural point of departure; it is legitimate, necessary, when applied to children of a tender age, whose intelligence has not yet openly developed itself. But as the development of everything, and consequently of education, implies the gradual negation of the point of departure, this principle must diminish as fast as education and instruction advance, giving place to increasing liberty. All rational education is at bottom nothing but this progressive immolation of authority for the benefit of liberty, the final object of education necessarily276being the formation of free men full of respect and love for the liberty of others. Therefore the first day of the pupil’s life, if the school takes infants scarcely able as yet to stammer a few words, should be that of the greatest authority and an almost entire absence of liberty; but its last day should be that of the greatest liberty and the absolute abolition of every vestige of the animal or divine principle of authority.
Eighty-
At this point you perhaps protest, “But if there is no compulsion, what happens if a child does not want to attend school of any kind, and the parents are not concerned to persuade him?” It is quite simple. In that case the child does not attend any school. As he becomes adolescent he may wish to acquire some learning. Or he may develop school-
going friends and wish to attend school because they do. But if he doesn’t he is nevertheless learning all the time, his natural child’s creativeness working in happy alliance with his freedom. No Utopian parent would think of using that moral coercion we call ‘persuasion’. By the time he reaches adolescence the child grows tired of running wild, and begins to identify himself with grown-
ups; he perceives the usefulness of knowing how to read and write and add, and there is probably some special thing he wants to learn—
such as how to drive a train or build a bridge or a house. It is all very much simpler than our professional educationists would have us believe.
Some of us think it is not that simple. But the point is academic, for in practice the decision is that of the parents. Nowadays it is only highly sophisticated and educated people who bother to argue about whether or not it is desirable that children should learn the three Rs. The law in this country does not in fact require parents to send their children to school; it imposes an obligation on them to see that their children while within the compulsory age, are receiving “an appropriate education”. The occasional prosecutions of recalcitrant parents usually reveal a degree of apathy, indifference or parental incompetence that hardly provides a good case for the opponents of compulsion, though they do sometimes rope in highly conscientious parents whose views on education do not happen to coincide with those of the local authority. (Mrs. Joy Baker’s account of her long and in the end successful struggle with the authorities will be reviewed in a coming issue of anarchy). Usually, apart from a few of the rich, with their governesses and tutors, there are not many parents with the time or skill to teach their children at home, and of those who could, many must feel it unfair to deprive their children of the pleasures and social experience of belonging to a community of their peers, or may cherish the right of parents to have the kids out of their way for some of the time—
The notion that primary ecucation should be free, compulsory and universal is very much older than the English Act of 1870. It grew up with the printing press and the rise of protestantism. The rich had been educated by the Church and the sons of the rising bourgeoisie in the grammar schools of the Middle Ages. From the 16th century on arose a gradual demand that all should be taught. Martin Luther appealed “To the Councilmen of all Cities in Germany that they establish and maintain Christian Schools”, observing that the training children get at home “attempts to make up wise through our experience” a task for which life itself is too short, and which could be accelerated by systematic instruction by means of books. Compulsory universal education was founded in Calvinist Geneva in 1536, and Calvin’s Scottish disciple John Knox “planted a school as well as a kirk in every parish.” In puritan Massachusetts free compulsory primary education was introduced in 1647. The common school, writes Lewis Mumford in The Condition of Man:
… contrary to popular belief, is no belated product of 19th century democracy: I have pointed out that it played a necessary part in the absolutist-
mechanical formula. Friedrich Wilhelm I of Prussia, following Luther’s precept, made primary education compulsory in his realm in 1717, and founded 1,700 schools to meet the needs of the poor. Two ordinances of Louis XIV in 1694 and 1698 and one of Louis XV in 1724 required regular attendance at school. Even England, a straggler in such matters, had hundreds of private charity schools, some of them founded by the Society for Promoting Christian Knowledge, which had been incorporated in 1699. Vergerious, one of the earliest renaissance schoolmasters, had thought education an essential function of the State; and centralised authority was now belatedly taking up the work that had been neglected with the wiping out of municipal freedom in the greater part of Europe.
All the rationalist philosophers of the 18th century thought about the problems of education, and of them, the two acutest educational thinkers ranged themselves on opposite sides on the question of the organisation of education: Rousseau for the State, Godwin against it. Rousseau, whose Emile postulates a completely individual education (human society is ignored, the tutor’s entire life is devoted to poor Emile), did nevertheless concern himself with the social aspect, arguing, in his Discourse on Political Economy (1755) for public education “under regulations prescribed by the government”, for
If children are brought up in common in the bosom of equality; if they are imbued with the laws of the State and the precepts of the General Will … we cannot doubt that they will cherish one another mutually as brothers … to become in time defenders and fathers of the country of which they will have been so long the children.