Difference between revisions of "Anarchy 31/Randolph Bourne vs. the State"
(7 intermediate revisions by 3 users not shown) | |||
Line 5: | Line 5: | ||
| previous = [[../|Contents of No. 31]] | | previous = [[../|Contents of No. 31]] | ||
| next = [[../Anarchism and the cybernetics of self-organising systems|Anarchism and the cybernetics of self-organising systems]] | | next = [[../Anarchism and the cybernetics of self-organising systems|Anarchism and the cybernetics of self-organising systems]] | ||
− | | notes = ''H. W. | + | | notes = ''H. W. MORTON is a New York anarchist who, with [[Author:Sam Weiner|Sam Weiner]], wrote {{qq|[[Anarchy 19/Were they way out way back?|Were they way out, way back?]]}} in'' [[Anarchy 19|{{sc|Anarchy}} 19]]. |
}} | }} | ||
Line 16: | Line 16: | ||
− | {{p|s1}}<div style="text-align:justify;">{{qq|{{sc|War is the health of the State}}.}} Had {{w|Randolph Bourne|Randolph_Bourne}} never written another line he would have earned immor­tal­ity from those words alone. {{qq|War is the health of the State,}} he an­nounced, and went on to explain: | + | {{p|s1|n}}<div style="text-align:justify;">{{qq|{{sc|War is the health of the State}}.}} Had {{w|Randolph Bourne|Randolph_Bourne}} never written another line he would have earned immor­tal­ity from those words alone. {{qq|War is the health of the State,}} he an­nounced, and went on to explain: |
− | <blockquote>{{tab}}{{qq|It auto­matic­ally sets in motion through­out society those irres­ist­ible forces for uni­form­ity, for pas­sion­ate co- | + | <blockquote>{{tab}}{{qq|It auto­matic­ally sets in motion through­out society those irres­ist­ible forces for uni­form­ity, for pas­sion­ate co-opera­tion with the Govern­ment in coer­cing into obedi­ence the minor­ity groups and indi­vidu­als which lack the larger herd sense. The ma­chinery of Govern­ment sets and en­forces the drastic penal­ties; the minor­ities are either intim­id­ated into silence, or brought slowly around by a subtle process of per­sua­sion which may seem to them really to be con­vert­ing them. Of course the ideal of perfect loyalty, perfect uni­form­ity is never really at­tained. The classes upon whom the amateur work of coer­cion falls are un­wearied in their zeal, but often their agita­tion instead of con­vert­ing, merely serves to stiffen their resist­ance. Minor­ities are rendered sullen, and some intel­lec­tual opinion bitter and satir­ical. But in general, the nation in war-time attains a uni­form­ity of feeling, a hier­archy of values cul­minat­ing at the undis­puted apex of the State ideal, which could not possibly be pro­duced through any other agency than war.}}</blockquote> |
− | {{tab}}Randolph Bourne, a bril­liant cripple, was born in {{w|New Jersey|New_Jersey}} in that singu­larly radical year 1886, and died in {{w|New York City|New_York_City}} in 1918. A gradu­ate of {{w|Columbia University|Columbia_Uni­ver­sity}}, and a member of that nebu­lous clique of {{w|Green­wich Village|Greenwich_Village}} {{w|Bohemi­ans|Bohemianism}}, he was a fre­quent con­trib­utor to ''{{w|The New Repub­lic|The_New_Republic}}'', ''{{w|The At­lantic Monthly|The_Atlantic}}'', ''{{w|The Seven Arts|The_Seven_Arts}}'' and ''{{w|The Dial|The_Dial}}''<!-- 'Dial' not in italics in original -->. Most of his writing, however, would be of little in­terest to anar­ | + | {{tab}}Randolph Bourne, a bril­liant cripple, was born in {{w|New Jersey|New_Jersey}} in that singu­larly radical year 1886, and died in {{w|New York City|New_York_City}} in 1918. A gradu­ate of {{w|Columbia University|Columbia_Uni­ver­sity}}, and a member of that nebu­lous clique of {{w|Green­wich Village|Greenwich_Village}} {{w|Bohemi­ans|Bohemianism|Bohemianism}}, he was a fre­quent con­trib­utor to ''{{w|The New Repub­lic|The_New_Republic}}'', ''{{w|The At­lantic Monthly|The_Atlantic|The Atlantic}}'', ''{{w|The Seven Arts|The_Seven_Arts}}'' and ''{{w|The Dial|The_Dial}}''<!-- 'Dial' not in italics in original -->. Most of his writing, however, would be of little in­terest to anar­chists—I found {{qq|{{l|The History of a Liter­ary Radical & Other Papers|https://archive.org/details/historyofliterar00bouruoft|Full text at the Internet Archive}}}} (New York, Russell, 1956) so uni­formly innoc­uous that I didn{{t}} even finish it. On the other hand, had this col­lec­tion in­cluded {{qq|{{l|The State|http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/randolph-bourne-the-state|Full text at the Anarchist Library}}}}, I would have no com­plaint, for {{qq|The State}} is the health­iest of Randolph Bourne. |
− | {{tab}}{{qq|The State}}, an un­fin­ished essay written at the time of {{w|World War I|World_War_I}}, had long been out of print. It has re­cently been re­ | + | {{tab}}{{qq|The State}}, an un­fin­ished essay written at the time of {{w|World War I|World_War_I}}, had long been out of print. It has re­cently been re­issued—in time for World War III—by the Greater New York Society for the Pre­ven­tion of Cruelty to the Human Animal, 150 Nassau Street, New York 38, N.Y. It is well worth the $1.00 price despite a rather bizarre format {{p|266}}({{popup|28 inches|71 cm}} wide, {{popup|8 inches|20 cm}} high when open). |
− | {{tab}}In its incom­plete form the essay defines the State, de­scribes its activ­ities, and dis­cusses its historic evolu­tion. Since it was never com­pleted, we cannot know what further treat­ment Bourne had planned. He might or might not have in­tended to pro­pose methods of abolish­ | + | {{tab}}In its incom­plete form the essay defines the State, de­scribes its activ­ities, and dis­cusses its historic evolu­tion. Since it was never com­pleted, we cannot know what further treat­ment Bourne had planned. He might or might not have in­tended to pro­pose methods of abolish­ing the State and discuss the pos­sibil­ities of a State­less society. From the content of the work itself, I would infer not. |
{{tab}}He begins with vigour and bril­liance: | {{tab}}He begins with vigour and bril­liance: | ||
Line 30: | Line 30: | ||
<blockquote>{{tab}}{{qq|Govern­ment is syn­onym­ous with neither State nor Nation. It is the ma­chinery by which the nation, organ­ized by a State, carries out its State func­tions. Govern­ment is a frame­work of the ad­minis­tra­tion of laws, and the carry­ing out of the public force. Govern­ment is the idea of the State put into prac­tical opera­tion in the hands of def­inite, con­crete, fal­lible men. It is the visible sign of the in­visible grace. It is the word made flesh.}}</blockquote> | <blockquote>{{tab}}{{qq|Govern­ment is syn­onym­ous with neither State nor Nation. It is the ma­chinery by which the nation, organ­ized by a State, carries out its State func­tions. Govern­ment is a frame­work of the ad­minis­tra­tion of laws, and the carry­ing out of the public force. Govern­ment is the idea of the State put into prac­tical opera­tion in the hands of def­inite, con­crete, fal­lible men. It is the visible sign of the in­visible grace. It is the word made flesh.}}</blockquote> | ||
− | Then after this beauti­fully anarch­istic begin­ning, Bourne im­medi­ately dis­appoints us: {{qq|And it has neces­sarily the lim­ita­tions inher­ent in all prac­tical­ity.}} Imagine attack­ing Govern­ment on the basis of prac­tical lim­ita­tions! I can no more con­ceive of an anarch­ist writing that, than of a paci­fist com­plain­ing that {{w|Hydro­gen Bombs|Thermonuclear_weapon}} are no good because they don{{t}} work. | + | Then after this beauti­fully anarch­istic begin­ning, Bourne im­medi­ately dis­appoints us: {{qq|And it has neces­sarily the lim­ita­tions inher­ent in all prac­tical­ity.}} Imagine attack­ing Govern­ment on the basis of prac­tical lim­ita­tions! I can no more con­ceive of an anarch­ist writing that, than of a paci­fist com­plain­ing that {{w|Hydro­gen Bombs|Thermonuclear_weapon|Thermonuclear weapon}} are no good because they don{{t}} work. |
− | {{tab}}However, Bourne im­medi­ately redeems himself by point­ing out that Govern­ment {{qq|is by no means ident­ical with}} the State. He empha­sizes the fact that the State is an ab­scrac­tion where­as Govern­ment is tan­gible. {{qq|That the State is a mys­tical concep­tion is some­thing that must never be for­gotten. Its glamour and its signi­fic­ance linger behind the frame­work of Govern­ment and direct its activ­ities.}} Here Bourne has put his finger on a crit­ical dis­tinc­ | + | {{tab}}However, Bourne im­medi­ately redeems himself by point­ing out that Govern­ment {{qq|is by no means ident­ical with}} the State. He empha­sizes the fact that the State is an ab­scrac­tion where­as Govern­ment is tan­gible. {{qq|That the State is a mys­tical concep­tion is some­thing that must never be for­gotten. Its glamour and its signi­fic­ance linger behind the frame­work of Govern­ment and direct its activ­ities.}} Here Bourne has put his finger on a crit­ical dis­tinc­tion—one which few people other than anarch­ists seem to grasp. |
{{tab}}''Society'' is the sum total of all the rela­tion­ships, com­bina­tions, as­socia­tions, insti­tu­tions, etc. of human beings in an inde­term­inate ter­rit­ory. ''The State'' is an in­volun­tary legal rela­tion­ship where­by a supreme author­ity has control over all persons and prop­erty in a speci­fic­ally bounded ter­rit­ory. ''Govern­ment'' is merely the mechan­ism of that legal rela­tion­ship. In other words, Govern­ment is an opera­ting body, con­stitut­ing only part of the over­all legal rela­tion­ship called the State. Simil­arly the State is but one rela­tion­ship among all the in­numer­able rela­tion­ships which com­prise Society. Con­versely, Society in­cludes the State; and the State in­cludes the Govern­ment. The confu­sion over the terms, and the temp­ta­tion to inter­change them, arises because Govern­ment is the most prom­inent part of the State, which in turn is the most power­ful rela­tion­ship of Society. | {{tab}}''Society'' is the sum total of all the rela­tion­ships, com­bina­tions, as­socia­tions, insti­tu­tions, etc. of human beings in an inde­term­inate ter­rit­ory. ''The State'' is an in­volun­tary legal rela­tion­ship where­by a supreme author­ity has control over all persons and prop­erty in a speci­fic­ally bounded ter­rit­ory. ''Govern­ment'' is merely the mechan­ism of that legal rela­tion­ship. In other words, Govern­ment is an opera­ting body, con­stitut­ing only part of the over­all legal rela­tion­ship called the State. Simil­arly the State is but one rela­tion­ship among all the in­numer­able rela­tion­ships which com­prise Society. Con­versely, Society in­cludes the State; and the State in­cludes the Govern­ment. The confu­sion over the terms, and the temp­ta­tion to inter­change them, arises because Govern­ment is the most prom­inent part of the State, which in turn is the most power­ful rela­tion­ship of Society. | ||
− | {{tab}}Without a clear under­stand­ing of these terms and their exact inter- | + | {{tab}}Without a clear under­stand­ing of these terms and their exact inter-rela­tion­ship, anarch­ist theory becomes incom­pre­hens­ible. When we anarch­ists attack the State we don{{t}} want to destroy society, injure govern­ment em­ploy­ees, or even demol­ish their office build­ings. Con­trast­ing the millennia<!-- 'millenia' in original --> of society{{s}}<!-- 'society's'' in original --> growth and de­velop­ment without the State to the im­min­ent pro­spect of uni­versal death with it, we have con­cluded that the State is but a re­mov­able malig­nant tumour on the {{p|267}}body social. There­fore we want to abolish the vicious power ar­range­ment by which we are domin­ated polit­ic­ally, ex­ploited eco­nomic­ally, and jeop­ard­ized phys­ic­ally. |
{{tab}}For the most part Bourne goes along with us. The fol­low­ing, for ex­ample, is fine anarch­istic ana­lysis: | {{tab}}For the most part Bourne goes along with us. The fol­low­ing, for ex­ample, is fine anarch­istic ana­lysis: | ||
− | <blockquote>{{tab}}{{qq|What is the State essen­tially? The more closely we examine it, the more mys­tical and per­sonal it becomes. On the Nation we can put our hand as a defin­ite social group, with atti­tudes and quan­ti­ties exact enough to mean some­thing. On the Govern­ment we can put our hand as a certain organ­isa­tion of ruling func­tions, the ma­chinery of law- | + | <blockquote>{{tab}}{{qq|What is the State essen­tially? The more closely we examine it, the more mys­tical and per­sonal it becomes. On the Nation we can put our hand as a defin­ite social group, with atti­tudes and quan­ti­ties exact enough to mean some­thing. On the Govern­ment we can put our hand as a certain organ­isa­tion of ruling func­tions, the ma­chinery of law-making and law-enforcing. The Ad­minis­tra­tion is a recog­niz­able group of polit­ical func­tion­aries, tempor­arily in charge of the Govern­ment. But the State stands as an idea behind them all, eternal, sanct­ified, and from it Govern­ment and Ad­minis­tra­tion con­ceive them­selves to have the breath of life. Even the nation, espe­cially in times of war—or at least, its signi­fic­ant classes—con­siders that it derives its author­ity and its purpose from the idea of the State. Nation and State are scarcely dif­fer­enti­ated, and the con­crete, prac­tical, ap­parent facts are sunk in the symbol. We rever­ence not our country but the flag. We may criti­cize ever so severely our country, but we are dis­respect­ful to the flag at our peril.}}</blockquote> |
+ | {{tab}}On the other hand some of Bourne{{s}} termin­ology is dis­turb­ing: he per­sist­ently uses {{qq|herd}}, al­though he con­tends that {{qq|there is nothing invidi­ous in the use of the term.}} He also refers occa­sion­ally to the {{qq|signi­fic­ant classes}}. Yet he is not neces­sarily élitist, for it is en­tirely pos­sible that he is viewing people with sym­pathy rather than scorn. Thus, al­though he speaks of the State being {{qq|the organ­isa­tion of the herd to act offens­ively or defens­ively against another herd simil­arly organ­ized}} and points out how it {{qq|becomes an instru­ment by which the power of the whole herd is wielded for the benefit of a class,}} he may be writing more in com­pas­sion than con­tempt. I am willing to give him the benefit of the doubt in view of his opinion that the working classes {{qq|live habitu­ally in an indus­trial serfdom, by which though nomin­ally free, they are in prac­tice as a class bound to a system of a machine-produc­tion the imple­ments of which they do not own, and in the dis­tribu­tion of whose product they have not the slight­est voice {{e}} From such serfdom, milit­ary {{w|con­scrip­tion|Conscription|Conscription}} is not so great a change.}} | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{tab}}Anarch­ists might also be irked by the treat­ment Bourne accords man{{s}} gregari­ous in­stinct. Here too, however, he might not be derid­ing mutual aid so much as com­plain­ing of how the State brutal­izes us<!-- 'is' in original -->: {{qq|In this great herd-ma­chinery, dissent is like sand in the bear­ings. The State ideal is primar­ily a sort of blind animal push towards milit­ary unity.}} I wish I could decide whether his anger is direc­ted solely at the State or if it in­cludes human­ity as well, ''e.g.'': | ||
+ | |||
+ | <blockquote>{{tab}}{{qq|There is, of course, in the feeling towards the State a large element of pure filial mysti­cism {{e}} A people at War have become in the most literal sense obedi­ent, respect­ful, trust­ful chil­dren again, full of that naive faith in the all-wisdom and all-power of the adult who takes care of them, imposes his mild but neces­sary rule upon {{p|268}} them{{e|r}}|l}}</blockquote> | ||
+ | |||
+ | <blockquote>{{tab}}{{qq|In your re­action to an ima­gined attack on your country or an insult to its Govern­ment, you draw closer to the herd for pro­tec­tion, you conform in word and deed, and you insist vehem­ently that every­body else shall think, speak and act to­gether.}}</blockquote> | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{tab}}Even if Bourne was closer to {{w|Nietzsche|Friedrich_Nietzsche|Friedrich Nietzsche}} than to {{w|Bakunin|Mikhail_Bakunin|Mikhail Bakunin}}, his criti­cisms are devast­ating: | ||
+ | |||
+ | <blockquote>{{tab}}{{qq|The State is a jealous god and will brook no rivals. Its sover­eignty<!-- 'severeignty' in original --> must pervade every­one and all feeling must be run into the stereo­typed forms of ro­mantic patri­otic milit­arism which is the tradi­tional ex­pres­sion of the State herd feeling.}} {{e}}</blockquote> | ||
+ | |||
+ | <blockquote>{{tab}}{{qq|The State moves inevitably along the line from {{w|milit­ary dic­tator­ship|Military_dictatorship|Military dictatorship}} to the {{w|divine right of Kings|Divine_right_of_kings|Divine right of kings}}. What had to be at first rawly imposed becomes through social habit to seem the neces­sary, the inevit­able.}} {{e}}</blockquote> | ||
+ | |||
+ | <blockquote>{{tab}}{{qq|Govern­ment [by the time of {{w|George III|George_III_of_the_United_Kingdom}}] had been for long what it has never ceased to be—a series of berths and emolu­ments in Army, Navy, and the differ­ent depart­ments of State, for the repres­entat­ives of the priv­ileged classes.}}</blockquote> | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{tab}}Judging solely from this essay I surmise that Bourne has never read any of the anarch­ist theor­eti­cians,<!-- '.' in original --> or if he did, that not much had rubbed off. (Still, his milieu prob­ably in­cluded a few anarch­ists). Assum­ing this essay to be an en­tirely inde­pend­ent crea­tion, it becomes all the more remark­able for its origin­ality and insight. On the other hand much of his bril­liance is wasted in ex­ploring ground already covered quite thor­oughly by numer­ous anarch­ists before him. For 150 years anarch­ist theor­eti­cians had been build­ing up a vast body of know­ledge on the State. No one indi­vidual, even one so penet­rating as Bourne, could pos­sibly match that century and a half of evolu­tion by himself. Had he taken con­tempor­ary anarch­ist think­ing as a point of depar­ture, there is no telling what he might have achieved. For example, his treat­ment of the State{{s}} his­toric de­velop­ment—the weakest part of the essay—would have been con­sider­ably en­hanced had he studied [[Author:Peter Kropotkin|Kropotkin]]. Con­versely, Kropotkin could have benefit­ted from reading Bourne on War: | ||
+ | |||
+ | <blockquote>{{tab}}{{qq|The State is intim­ately con­nected with war, for it is the organ­iza­tion of the col­lect­ive com­mun­ity when it acts in a polit­ical manner, and to act in a polit­ical manner towards a rival group has meant, through­out history—war.{{e|r}}|l}}</blockquote> | ||
+ | |||
+ | <blockquote>{{tab}}{{qq|It is States that makes wars and not nations, and the very thought and almost neces­sity of war is bound up with the ideal of the State {{e}} for war implies an organ­ized people drilled and led; in fact it neces­si­tates the State.}}</blockquote> | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{tab}}War for Bourne is not a con­tinua­tion of dip­lomacy—rather, {{qq|dip­lomacy is a dis­guised war.}} | ||
+ | |||
+ | <blockquote>{{tab}}{{qq|{{e|l}}for the last strong­hold of State power is foreign policy. It is in foreign policy that the State acts most con­cen­tratedly as the organ­ized herd, acts with fullest sense of ag­gres­sive power, acts with freest arbit­rari­ness. In foreign policy, the State is most itself. {{p|269}}States, with refer­ence to each other, may be said to be in a con­tinual state of latent war. The {{q|armed truce}}, a phrase so famil­iar before 1914, was an accur­ate descrip­tion of the normal rela­tion of States when they are not at war. Indeed, it is not too much to say that the normal rela­tions of States is war. Dip­lomacy is a dis­guised war, in which States seek to gain by barter and in­trigue, by the clever­ness of wit, the object­ives which they would have to gain more clumsily by means of war. Dip­lomacy is used while the States are recuper­ating from con­flicts in which they have ex­hausted them­selves. It is the wheed­ling and the bargain­ing of the worn-out bullies as they rise from the ground and slowly restore their strength to begin fight­ing again. If dip­lomacy had been the moral equi­valent for war, a higher stage in human progress, an in­estim­able means of making words prevail instead of blows, milit­arism would have broken down and given place to it. But since it is a mere tempor­ary sub­sti­tute, a mere appear­ance of war{{s}} energy under another form, a sur­rog­ate effect is almost exactly pro­por­tioned to the armed force behind it. When it fails, the re­course is im­medi­ate to the milit­ary tech­nique whose thinly veiled arm it has been. A dip­lomacy that was the agency of popular demo­cratic forces in their non-State mani­festa­tions would be no dip­lomacy at all. It would be no better than the Railway or Educa­tion Com­mis­sions that are sent from one country to another with rational con­struct­ive purpose. The State, acting as a dip­lomatic-milit­ary ideal, is etern­ally at war.{{e|r}}}}</blockquote> | ||
+ | |||
+ | <blockquote>{{tab}}{{qq|It cannot be too firmly real­ized that war is a func­tion of States and not of nations, indeed that is the chief func­tion of States. War is a very arti­ficial thing. It is not the naive spon­tan­eous outburst of herd pug­nacity; it is no more primary than is formal religion. War cannot exist without a milit­ary estab­lish­ment, and a milit­ary estab­lish­ment cannot exist without a State organ­iza­tion. War has an imme­morial tradi­tion and hered­ity only because the State has a long tradi­tion and hered­ity. But they are in­separ­ably and func­tion­ally joined. ''We cannot crusade against war without crusad­ing impli­citly against the State.'' (My emphasis—H.W.M.). And we cannot expect or take meas­ures to insure, that this war is a war to end war, unless at the same time we take meas­ures to end that State in its tradi­tional form. The State is not the nation, and the State can be modi­fied and even abo­lished in its present form, without harming the nation. On the con­trary, with the passing of the domin­ance of the State, the genuine life-en­hancing forces of the nation will be liberated {{e}} For the very exist­ence of a State in a system of States means that the nation lies always under a risk of war and inva­sion, and the calling away of energy into milit­ary pur­suits means a crip­pling of the pro­duct­ive and life-en­hancing pro­cesses of the na­tional life.}}</blockquote> | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{tab}}In view of all the above senti­ments should we con­sider Bourne an anarch­ist, a paci­fist, both, or neither? Obvi­ously he had a genuine hatred both of the State and of war, but somehow I get the impres­sion that he was not ready to replace either the former with freedom, or the latter with love. | ||
{{DEFAULTSORT:Randolph Bourne versus the State}} | {{DEFAULTSORT:Randolph Bourne versus the State}} |
Latest revision as of 10:38, 11 October 2021
Randolph Bourne vs. the State
“It automatically sets in motion throughout society those irresistible forces for uniformity, for passionate co-operation with the Government in coercing into obedience the minority groups and individuals which lack the larger herd sense. The machinery of Government sets and enforces the drastic penalties; the minorities are either intimidated into silence, or brought slowly around by a subtle process of persuasion which may seem to them really to be converting them. Of course the ideal of perfect loyalty, perfect uniformity is never really attained. The classes upon whom the amateur work of coercion falls are unwearied in their zeal, but often their agitation instead of converting, merely serves to stiffen their resistance. Minorities are rendered sullen, and some intellectual opinion bitter and satirical. But in general, the nation in war-time attains a uniformity of feeling, a hierarchy of values culminating at the undisputed apex of the State ideal, which could not possibly be produced through any other agency than war.”
Randolph Bourne, a brilliant cripple, was born in New Jersey in that singularly radical year 1886, and died in New York City in 1918. A graduate of Columbia University, and a member of that nebulous clique of Greenwich Village Bohemians, he was a frequent contributor to The New Republic, The Atlantic Monthly, The Seven Arts and The Dial. Most of his writing, however, would be of little interest to anarchists—I found “The History of a Literary Radical & Other Papers” (New York, Russell, 1956) so uniformly innocuous that I didn’t even finish it. On the other hand, had this collection included “The State”, I would have no complaint, for “The State” is the healthiest of Randolph Bourne.
“The State”, an unfinished essay written at the time of World War I, had long been out of print. It has recently been reissued—in time for World War III—by the Greater New York Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to the Human Animal, 150 Nassau Street, New York 38, N.Y. It is well worth the $1.00 price despite a rather bizarre formatIn its incomplete form the essay defines the State, describes its activities, and discusses its historic evolution. Since it was never completed, we cannot know what further treatment Bourne had planned. He might or might not have intended to propose methods of abolishing the State and discuss the possibilities of a Stateless society. From the content of the work itself, I would infer not.
He begins with vigour and brilliance:
“Government is synonymous with neither State nor Nation. It is the machinery by which the nation, organized by a State, carries out its State functions. Government is a framework of the administration of laws, and the carrying out of the public force. Government is the idea of the State put into practical operation in the hands of definite, concrete, fallible men. It is the visible sign of the invisible grace. It is the word made flesh.”
Then after this beautifully anarchistic beginning, Bourne immediately disappoints us: “And it has necessarily the limitations inherent in all practicality.” Imagine attacking Government on the basis of practical limitations! I can no more conceive of an anarchist writing that, than of a pacifist complaining that Hydrogen Bombs are no good because they don’t work.
However, Bourne immediately redeems himself by pointing out that Government “is by no means identical with” the State. He emphasizes the fact that the State is an abscraction whereas Government is tangible. “That the State is a mystical conception is something that must never be forgotten. Its glamour and its significance linger behind the framework of Government and direct its activities.” Here Bourne has put his finger on a critical distinction—one which few people other than anarchists seem to grasp.
Society is the sum total of all the relationships, combinations, associations, institutions, etc. of human beings in an indeterminate territory. The State is an involuntary legal relationship whereby a supreme authority has control over all persons and property in a specifically bounded territory. Government is merely the mechanism of that legal relationship. In other words, Government is an operating body, constituting only part of the overall legal relationship called the State. Similarly the State is but one relationship among all the innumerable relationships which comprise Society. Conversely, Society includes the State; and the State includes the Government. The confusion over the terms, and the temptation to interchange them, arises because Government is the most prominent part of the State, which in turn is the most powerful relationship of Society.
Without a clear understanding of these terms and their exact inter-relationship, anarchist theory becomes incomprehensible. When we anarchists attack the State we don’t want to destroy society, injure government employees, or even demolish their office buildings. Contrasting the millennia of society’s growth and development without the State to the imminent prospect of universal death with it, we have concluded that the State is but a removable malignant tumour on theFor the most part Bourne goes along with us. The following, for example, is fine anarchistic analysis:
“What is the State essentially? The more closely we examine it, the more mystical and personal it becomes. On the Nation we can put our hand as a definite social group, with attitudes and quantities exact enough to mean something. On the Government we can put our hand as a certain organisation of ruling functions, the machinery of law-making and law-enforcing. The Administration is a recognizable group of political functionaries, temporarily in charge of the Government. But the State stands as an idea behind them all, eternal, sanctified, and from it Government and Administration conceive themselves to have the breath of life. Even the nation, especially in times of war—or at least, its significant classes—considers that it derives its authority and its purpose from the idea of the State. Nation and State are scarcely differentiated, and the concrete, practical, apparent facts are sunk in the symbol. We reverence not our country but the flag. We may criticize ever so severely our country, but we are disrespectful to the flag at our peril.”
On the other hand some of Bourne’s terminology is disturbing: he persistently uses “herd”, although he contends that “there is nothing invidious in the use of the term.” He also refers occasionally to the “significant classes”. Yet he is not necessarily élitist, for it is entirely possible that he is viewing people with sympathy rather than scorn. Thus, although he speaks of the State being “the organisation of the herd to act offensively or defensively against another herd similarly organized” and points out how it “becomes an instrument by which the power of the whole herd is wielded for the benefit of a class,” he may be writing more in compassion than contempt. I am willing to give him the benefit of the doubt in view of his opinion that the working classes “live habitually in an industrial serfdom, by which though nominally free, they are in practice as a class bound to a system of a machine-production the implements of which they do not own, and in the distribution of whose product they have not the slightest voice . . . From such serfdom, military conscription is not so great a change.”
Anarchists might also be irked by the treatment Bourne accords man’s gregarious instinct. Here too, however, he might not be deriding mutual aid so much as complaining of how the State brutalizes us: “In this great herd-machinery, dissent is like sand in the bearings. The State ideal is primarily a sort of blind animal push towards military unity.” I wish I could decide whether his anger is directed solely at the State or if it includes humanity as well, e.g.:
“There is, of course, in the feeling towards the State a large element of pure filial mysticism . . . A people at War have become in the most literal sense obedient, respectful, trustful children again, full of that naive faith in the all-wisdom and all-power of the adult who takes care of them, imposes his mild but necessary rule upon
268them . . .
“In your reaction to an imagined attack on your country or an insult to its Government, you draw closer to the herd for protection, you conform in word and deed, and you insist vehemently that everybody else shall think, speak and act together.”
Even if Bourne was closer to Nietzsche than to Bakunin, his criticisms are devastating:
“The State is a jealous god and will brook no rivals. Its sovereignty must pervade everyone and all feeling must be run into the stereotyped forms of romantic patriotic militarism which is the traditional expression of the State herd feeling.” . . .
“The State moves inevitably along the line from military dictatorship to the divine right of Kings. What had to be at first rawly imposed becomes through social habit to seem the necessary, the inevitable.” . . .
“Government [by the time of George III] had been for long what it has never ceased to be—a series of berths and emoluments in Army, Navy, and the different departments of State, for the representatives of the privileged classes.”
Judging solely from this essay I surmise that Bourne has never read any of the anarchist theoreticians, or if he did, that not much had rubbed off. (Still, his milieu probably included a few anarchists). Assuming this essay to be an entirely independent creation, it becomes all the more remarkable for its originality and insight. On the other hand much of his brilliance is wasted in exploring ground already covered quite thoroughly by numerous anarchists before him. For 150 years anarchist theoreticians had been building up a vast body of knowledge on the State. No one individual, even one so penetrating as Bourne, could possibly match that century and a half of evolution by himself. Had he taken contemporary anarchist thinking as a point of departure, there is no telling what he might have achieved. For example, his treatment of the State’s historic development—the weakest part of the essay—would have been considerably enhanced had he studied Kropotkin. Conversely, Kropotkin could have benefitted from reading Bourne on War:
“The State is intimately connected with war, for it is the organization of the collective community when it acts in a political manner, and to act in a political manner towards a rival group has meant, throughout history—war. . . .
“It is States that makes wars and not nations, and the very thought and almost necessity of war is bound up with the ideal of the State . . . for war implies an organized people drilled and led; in fact it necessitates the State.”
War for Bourne is not a continuation of diplomacy—rather, “diplomacy is a disguised war.”
“. . . for the last stronghold of State power is foreign policy. It is in foreign policy that the State acts most concentratedly as the organized herd, acts with fullest sense of aggressive power, acts with freest arbitrariness. In foreign policy, the State is most itself.
269States, with reference to each other, may be said to be in a continual state of latent war. The ‘armed truce’, a phrase so familiar before 1914, was an accurate description of the normal relation of States when they are not at war. Indeed, it is not too much to say that the normal relations of States is war. Diplomacy is a disguised war, in which States seek to gain by barter and intrigue, by the cleverness of wit, the objectives which they would have to gain more clumsily by means of war. Diplomacy is used while the States are recuperating from conflicts in which they have exhausted themselves. It is the wheedling and the bargaining of the worn-out bullies as they rise from the ground and slowly restore their strength to begin fighting again. If diplomacy had been the moral equivalent for war, a higher stage in human progress, an inestimable means of making words prevail instead of blows, militarism would have broken down and given place to it. But since it is a mere temporary substitute, a mere appearance of war’s energy under another form, a surrogate effect is almost exactly proportioned to the armed force behind it. When it fails, the recourse is immediate to the military technique whose thinly veiled arm it has been. A diplomacy that was the agency of popular democratic forces in their non-State manifestations would be no diplomacy at all. It would be no better than the Railway or Education Commissions that are sent from one country to another with rational constructive purpose. The State, acting as a diplomatic-military ideal, is eternally at war. . . .”
“It cannot be too firmly realized that war is a function of States and not of nations, indeed that is the chief function of States. War is a very artificial thing. It is not the naive spontaneous outburst of herd pugnacity; it is no more primary than is formal religion. War cannot exist without a military establishment, and a military establishment cannot exist without a State organization. War has an immemorial tradition and heredity only because the State has a long tradition and heredity. But they are inseparably and functionally joined. We cannot crusade against war without crusading implicitly against the State. (My emphasis—H.W.M.). And we cannot expect or take measures to insure, that this war is a war to end war, unless at the same time we take measures to end that State in its traditional form. The State is not the nation, and the State can be modified and even abolished in its present form, without harming the nation. On the contrary, with the passing of the dominance of the State, the genuine life-enhancing forces of the nation will be liberated . . . For the very existence of a State in a system of States means that the nation lies always under a risk of war and invasion, and the calling away of energy into military pursuits means a crippling of the productive and life-enhancing processes of the national life.”
In view of all the above sentiments should we consider Bourne an anarchist, a pacifist, both, or neither? Obviously he had a genuine hatred both of the State and of war, but somehow I get the impression that he was not ready to replace either the former with freedom, or the latter with love.