Difference between revisions of "Anarchy 70/Libertarian Psychiatry: an introduction to existential analysis"

From Anarchy
Jump to navigation Jump to search
imported>Ivanhoe
imported>Ivanhoe
Line 49: Line 49:
 
{{tab}}In 1965 there were 160,000 people in mental hos&shy;pitals in Britain and an estim&shy;ated 200,000 psy&shy;chotics in the com&shy;mun&shy;ity. Nearly half of all hos&shy;pital beds are oc&shy;cu&shy;pied my the men&shy;tally ill. In a tele&shy;vision pro&shy;gramme on mental health<ref>{{w|BBC}} {{qq|{{w|Panorama|Panorama_(TV_series)}}}} on {{qq|Mental Health}}, 6th June, 1966.</ref> the number of men&shy;tally ill in Britain was given as half a million. The tele&shy;vised psy&shy;chi&shy;atrist sug&shy;gested that there were four main cat&shy;egor&shy;ies of ill&shy;ness: people with mental de&shy;form&shy;ity, {{p|357}}old people with {{qq|mental equip&shy;ment in de&shy;cline}} (&hellip; per&shy;haps old people with no&shy;where else to go?{{ref|aster2|**}}), people with physiolo&shy;gic&shy;ally normal mental equip&shy;ment but with ac&shy;quired neur&shy;otic pat&shy;terns, and lastly, vic&shy;tims of {{qq|bio{{-}}chem&shy;ical ill&shy;ness}}{{dash}}in his words, {{qq|Struck down out of the blue}}. The fourth cat&shy;egory per&shy;haps re&shy;flects, more than any&shy;thing else, the cur&shy;rently fa&shy;voured styles of treat&shy;ment!
 
{{tab}}In 1965 there were 160,000 people in mental hos&shy;pitals in Britain and an estim&shy;ated 200,000 psy&shy;chotics in the com&shy;mun&shy;ity. Nearly half of all hos&shy;pital beds are oc&shy;cu&shy;pied my the men&shy;tally ill. In a tele&shy;vision pro&shy;gramme on mental health<ref>{{w|BBC}} {{qq|{{w|Panorama|Panorama_(TV_series)}}}} on {{qq|Mental Health}}, 6th June, 1966.</ref> the number of men&shy;tally ill in Britain was given as half a million. The tele&shy;vised psy&shy;chi&shy;atrist sug&shy;gested that there were four main cat&shy;egor&shy;ies of ill&shy;ness: people with mental de&shy;form&shy;ity, {{p|357}}old people with {{qq|mental equip&shy;ment in de&shy;cline}} (&hellip; per&shy;haps old people with no&shy;where else to go?{{ref|aster2|**}}), people with physiolo&shy;gic&shy;ally normal mental equip&shy;ment but with ac&shy;quired neur&shy;otic pat&shy;terns, and lastly, vic&shy;tims of {{qq|bio{{-}}chem&shy;ical ill&shy;ness}}{{dash}}in his words, {{qq|Struck down out of the blue}}. The fourth cat&shy;egory per&shy;haps re&shy;flects, more than any&shy;thing else, the cur&shy;rently fa&shy;voured styles of treat&shy;ment!
  
{{tab}}By far the largest group is the third{{dash}}the {{qq|neur&shy;otics and psychot&shy;ics}}. Among these {{qq|{{w|schizo&shy;phrenia|Schizophrenia}}}} is the most common dia&shy;gnosis. {{qq|In most European coun&shy;tries about one per cent of the popu&shy;la&shy;tion go to hos&shy;pital at least once in their life&shy;time with the dia&shy;gnosis schizo&shy;phrenia.}}<ref>{{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}}, {{qq|The Anti{{-}}Hos&shy;pital: An Ex&shy;peri&shy;ment in Psy&shy;chi&shy;atry}}, {{w|''New So&shy;ciety''|New_Society}}, 11th March, 1965.</ref> But what mean&shy;ing can be given to these stat&shy;istics and as&shy;sess&shy;ments without a stand&shy;ard of san&shy;ity or mad&shy;ness? {{qq|Defin&shy;i&shy;tions of mental health pro&shy;pounded by the ex&shy;perts usually re&shy;duce to the no&shy;tion of con&shy;form&shy;ism, to a set of more or less ar&shy;bit&shy;rar&shy;ily pos&shy;ited so&shy;cial norms. &hellip;}}<ref>{{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}}, {{qq|Viol&shy;ence in Psy&shy;chi&shy;atry}}, ''{{l|Views|https://lccn.loc.gov/sf83002178}}'', No. 8, Summer, 1965.</ref> The label&shy;ling of people as mad can have the so&shy;cial func&shy;tion of defin&shy;ing the area of {{qq|san&shy;ity}}{{dash}}per&shy;haps there is a par&shy;al&shy;lel with {{w|Durkheim|Émile_Durkheim}}{{s}} theory of crime and pun&shy;ish&shy;ment as {{qq|neces&shy;sary}} to re&shy;spect&shy;able so&shy;ciety to mark off the limits of per&shy;mis&shy;sible and toler&shy;ated beha&shy;viour. {{qq|So&shy;ciety needs lun&shy;at&shy;ics in order that it may regard itself as sane.}}<ref>ibid.</ref> It could also be argued that cer&shy;tain kinds of so&shy;ciety {{qq|need}} lun&shy;at&shy;ics as their man&shy;agers; a dis&shy;cus&shy;sion in {{w|''Peace News''|Peace_News}} re&shy;cently was con&shy;cerned with the un&shy;certi&shy;fi&shy;able mad&shy;ness of the {{w|Amer&shy;ican Presid&shy;ent|Lyndon_B._Johnson}} in rela&shy;tion to a {{qq|col&shy;lect&shy;ive norm of in&shy;san&shy;ity}}. A Cor&shy;re&shy;spond&shy;ent noted: {{qq|No sig&shy;ni&shy;fic&shy;ant mem&shy;ber of a power estab&shy;lish&shy;ment can ever be {{q|cert&shy;ifi&shy;ably in&shy;sane}} since it is this same estab&shy;lish&shy;ment which de&shy;ter&shy;mines the defin&shy;i&shy;tions of {{q|san&shy;ity}} and {{q|in&shy;san&shy;ity}} and which de&shy;cides{{dash|checked only by the oc&shy;ca&shy;sional con&shy;science of an oc&shy;ca&shy;sional pro&shy;fes&shy;sional medi&shy;cal man}}when {{qq|in&shy;san&shy;ity}} becomes {{qq|{{w|cert&shy;ifi&shy;able|Involuntary_commitment}}}}.}}<ref>Part of a letter by Pierre{{-}}Joseph Brie, {{qq|In&shy;san&shy;ity and the Egg}}, {{w|''Peace News''|Peace_News}}, 1st July, 1966.</ref>
+
{{tab}}By far the largest group is the third{{dash}}the {{qq|neur&shy;otics and psychot&shy;ics}}. Among these {{qq|{{w|schizo&shy;phrenia|Schizophrenia}}}} is the most common dia&shy;gnosis. {{qq|In most European coun&shy;tries about one per cent of the popu&shy;la&shy;tion go to hos&shy;pital at least once in their life&shy;time with the dia&shy;gnosis schizo&shy;phrenia.}}<ref>{{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}}, {{qq|The Anti{{-}}Hos&shy;pital: An Ex&shy;peri&shy;ment in Psy&shy;chi&shy;atry}}, {{w|''New So&shy;ciety''|New_Society}}, 11th March, 1965.</ref> But what mean&shy;ing can be given to these stat&shy;istics and as&shy;sess&shy;ments without a stand&shy;ard of san&shy;ity or mad&shy;ness? {{qq|Defin&shy;i&shy;tions of mental health pro&shy;pounded by the ex&shy;perts usually re&shy;duce to the no&shy;tion of con&shy;form&shy;ism, to a set of more or less ar&shy;bit&shy;rar&shy;ily pos&shy;ited so&shy;cial norms. &hellip;}}<ref>{{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}}, {{qq|Viol&shy;ence in Psy&shy;chi&shy;atry}}, ''{{l|Views|https://lccn.loc.gov/sf83002178}}'', No. 8, Summer, 1965.</ref> The label&shy;ling of people as mad can have the so&shy;cial func&shy;tion of defin&shy;ing the area of {{qq|san&shy;ity}}{{dash}}per&shy;haps there is a par&shy;al&shy;lel with {{w|Durkheim|Émile_Durkheim}}{{s}} theory of crime and pun&shy;&shy;ish&shy;ment as {{qq|neces&shy;sary}} to re&shy;spect&shy;able so&shy;ciety to mark off the limits of per&shy;mis&shy;sible and toler&shy;ated beha&shy;viour. {{qq|So&shy;ciety needs lun&shy;at&shy;ics in order that it may regard itself as sane.}}<ref>ibid.</ref> It could also be argued that cer&shy;tain kinds of so&shy;ciety {{qq|need}} lun&shy;at&shy;ics as their man&shy;agers; a dis&shy;cus&shy;sion in {{w|''Peace News''|Peace_News}} re&shy;cently was con&shy;cerned with the un&shy;certi&shy;fi&shy;able mad&shy;ness of the {{w|Amer&shy;ican Presid&shy;ent|Lyndon_B._Johnson}} in rela&shy;tion to a {{qq|col&shy;lect&shy;ive norm of in&shy;san&shy;ity}}. A Cor&shy;re&shy;spond&shy;ent noted: {{qq|No sig&shy;ni&shy;fic&shy;ant mem&shy;ber of a power estab&shy;lish&shy;ment can ever be {{q|cert&shy;ifi&shy;ably in&shy;sane}} since it is this same estab&shy;lish&shy;ment which de&shy;ter&shy;mines the defin&shy;i&shy;tions of {{q|san&shy;ity}} and {{q|in&shy;san&shy;ity}} and which de&shy;cides{{dash|checked only by the oc&shy;ca&shy;sional con&shy;science of an oc&shy;ca&shy;sional pro&shy;fes&shy;sional medi&shy;cal man}}when {{qq|in&shy;san&shy;ity}} becomes {{qq|{{w|cert&shy;ifi&shy;able|Involuntary_commitment}}}}.}}<ref>Part of a letter by Pierre{{-}}Joseph Brie, {{qq|In&shy;san&shy;ity and the Egg}}, {{w|''Peace News''|Peace_News}}, 1st July, 1966.</ref>
  
{{tab}}In offi&shy;cial stat&shy;istics there must, in any case, be a murky over&shy;lap area between what comes out as {{qq|crime}} and what as {{qq|lunacy}}{{dash}}and a lot of luck in who ends up in which in&shy;stitu&shy;tion. Per&shy;haps it is the in&shy;stitu&shy;tional bureau&shy;cracy that has most need of the labels: {{qq|Ac&shy;cord&shy;ing to the common&shy;sense defin&shy;i&shy;tion,}} writes Dr. Theodore Szasz, {{qq|mental health is the abil&shy;ity to play what&shy;ever the game of so&shy;cial living might con&shy;sist of and to play it well. Con&shy;versely, to re&shy;fuse to play, or to play badly, means that the person is men&shy;tally ill. The ques&shy;tion may now be raised as to what are the dif&shy;fer&shy;ences, if any between so&shy;cial non&shy;con&shy;form&shy;ity (or devi&shy;a&shy;tion) and mental ill&shy;ness. Leaving tech&shy;nical psy&shy;chi&shy;atric con&shy;sider&shy;a&shy;tions aside for the moment, I shall argue that the dif&shy;fer&shy;ence between these two no&shy;tions{{dash|as ex&shy;pressed for ex&shy;ample by the state&shy;ments {{q|He is wrong}} and {{q|He is men&shy;tally ill}}}}does not lie in any ob&shy;serv&shy;able ''facts'' to which they may point, but may con&shy;sist only of a dif&shy;fer&shy;ence in our ''at&shy;ti&shy;tudes'' toward our sub&shy;ject.}}<ref>{{w|T. S. Szasz|Thomas_Szasz}}, {{qq|Polit&shy;ics and Mental Health}}, {{w|''Amer&shy;ican Journal of Psy&shy;chi&shy;atry''|American_Journal_of_Psychiatry}}, No. 115 (1958) (quoted by {{w|Erving Goffman|Erving_Goffman}} in {{w|''Asylums''|Asylums_(book)}}, p. 509).</ref> What sort of be&shy;ha&shy;viour is likely to lead those with the ap&shy;propri&shy;ate at&shy;ti&shy;tudes to see signs of mental ill&shy;ness and to set going the trans&shy;fer pro&shy;cess from {{p|358}}{{qq|person to pa&shy;tient}}? {{qq|Ordin&shy;arily the patho&shy;logy which first draws at&shy;ten&shy;tion to the pa&shy;tient{{s}} con&shy;di&shy;tion is con&shy;duct that is {{q|in&shy;ap&shy;propri&shy;ate in the situ&shy;a&shy;tion}}. &hellip; Further, since in&shy;ap&shy;propri&shy;ate beha&shy;viour is typic&shy;ally beha&shy;viour that some&shy;one does not like and finds ex&shy;tremely trouble&shy;some, deci&shy;sions con&shy;cern&shy;ing it tend to be polit&shy;ical, in the sense of ex&shy;pres&shy;sing the spe&shy;cial inter&shy;ests of some par&shy;tic&shy;u&shy;lar fac&shy;tion or person. &hellip;}}<ref>{{w|Erving Goffman|Erving_Goffman}}, ''{{w|Asylums{{dash}}Essays on the So&shy;cial Situ&shy;a&shy;tion of Mental Pa&shy;tients and Other In&shy;mates|Asylums_(book)}}'', New York, Anchor Books, 1961, pp. 363-4.</ref> As an ex&shy;ample of {{qq|in&shy;ap&shy;propri&shy;ate beha&shy;viour}}, con&shy;sider the case of {{qq|The Naked Prisoner}} ({{sc|{{w|freedom|Freedom_(newspaper)}}}}, 16.10.65). Mr. Paul Pawlowski was ar&shy;rested during a demon&shy;stra&shy;tion at the {{w|Spanish Embassy|Embassy_of_Spain,_London}} in {{w|London}}. Eventu&shy;ally reach&shy;ing {{w|Brixton Prison|HM_Prison_Brixton}}, he re&shy;fused to put on the stand&shy;ard pris&shy;on&shy;er{{s|r}} uni&shy;form and was con&shy;sequently locked up, naked, in his cell. Thus he re&shy;mained for ten days. On the tenth day he was inter&shy;viewed by a so&shy;cial worker: {{qq|&hellip; You know that two doctors have seen you while you have been in Brixton &hellip; they came to the con&shy;clu&shy;sion that what you need is a little stay in a mental hos&shy;pital.}} In fact he did not have the benefit of this con&shy;fine&shy;ment. The hos&shy;pital psy&shy;chi&shy;atrist de&shy;cided that Mr. Pawlowski{{s}} opin&shy;ions were not those of the ma&shy;jor&shy;ity but {{qq|people are not put into mental hos&shy;pitals for their opin&shy;ions. They do that sort of thing in {{w|Russia|Soviet_Union}}.}}{{ref|aster3|***}} Mr. Pawlowski was for&shy;tun&shy;ate in his psy&shy;chi&shy;atrist, but it is inter&shy;est&shy;ing to see how the pre{{-}}exist&shy;ing at&shy;ti&shy;tudes of offi&shy;cials brought him to the brink of ad&shy;mis&shy;sion. The overt polit&shy;ical im&shy;plica&shy;tions may make this ex&shy;ample ex&shy;cep&shy;tional{{dash|but it would not seem to be to the ad&shy;vant&shy;age of a person sus&shy;pected of mental ill&shy;ness to have been {{qq|mixed up in polit&shy;ics}} or {{qq|the dregs of so&shy;ciety in {{w|CND|Campaign_for_Nuclear_Disarmament}}}}}}which it seems, may well be taken as a con&shy;firm&shy;atory symp&shy;tom.{{ref|dagger|&dagger;}} The mental health service{{dash|like the edu&shy;ca&shy;tion {{qq|service}}}}is a func&shy;tional part of the present so&shy;cial system and, as such, acts to pre&shy;serve that system and its values. {{qq|The psy&shy;chi&shy;atric pro&shy;fes&shy;sion is a bureau&shy;cracy,}} writes James Green, a con&shy;trib&shy;utor to ''{{l|Views|https://lccn.loc.gov/sf83002178}}'', No. 8, {{qq|making an es&shy;sen&shy;tial con&shy;trib&shy;u&shy;tion to the run&shy;ning of gov&shy;ern&shy;ment and ad&shy;minis&shy;tra&shy;tion. &hellip; Most psy&shy;chi&shy;atrists would prob&shy;ably take for granted the struc&shy;ture and values of their own so&shy;ciety, in such a way that the thera&shy;peutic pro&shy;cess becomes a ques&shy;tion of re&shy;turn&shy;ing the sick person to his so&shy;cial con&shy;text or roles, e.g. his family, whether the con&shy;text and roles are them&shy;selves satis&shy;fact&shy;ory.}} Al&shy;though no doubt un&shy;repre&shy;sent&shy;at&shy;ive and redol&shy;ent of {{qq|what they do in Russia}} I can&shy;not resist quot&shy;ing the words of a psy&shy;chi&shy;atrist par&shy;ti&shy;cipant in a re&shy;cently tele&shy;vised dis&shy;cus&shy;sion: {{qq|Our func&shy;tion is to get people well enough to be in&shy;doc&shy;trin&shy;ated.}} It would be mis&shy;lead&shy;ing to sug&shy;gest that any&shy;thing but a tiny minor&shy;ity become in&shy;mates of asylums simply or only because they hold dis&shy;ap&shy;proved {{p|359}}opin&shy;ions, but pos&shy;sibly such cases may lead to a con&shy;sider&shy;a&shy;tion of the far more subtle {{qq|polit&shy;ical}} and so&shy;cial mean&shy;ing of the label&shy;ling and con&shy;fine&shy;ment of the un&shy;vocal ma&shy;jor&shy;ity.
+
{{tab}}In offi&shy;cial stat&shy;istics there must, in any case, be a murky over&shy;lap area between what comes out as {{qq|crime}} and what as {{qq|lunacy}}{{dash}}and a lot of luck in who ends up in which in&shy;stitu&shy;tion. Per&shy;haps it is the in&shy;stitu&shy;tional bureau&shy;cracy that has most need of the labels: {{qq|Ac&shy;cord&shy;ing to the common&shy;sense defin&shy;i&shy;tion,}} writes Dr. Theodore Szasz, {{qq|mental health is the abil&shy;ity to play what&shy;ever the game of so&shy;cial living might con&shy;sist of and to play it well. Con&shy;versely, to re&shy;fuse to play, or to play badly, means that the person is men&shy;tally ill. The ques&shy;tion may now be raised as to what are the dif&shy;fer&shy;ences, if any between so&shy;cial non&shy;con&shy;form&shy;ity (or devi&shy;a&shy;tion) and mental ill&shy;ness. Leaving tech&shy;nical psy&shy;chi&shy;atric con&shy;sider&shy;a&shy;tions aside for the moment, I shall argue that the dif&shy;fer&shy;ence between these two no&sh&shy;y;tions{{dash|as ex&shy;pressed for ex&shy;ample by the state&shy;ments {{q|He is wrong}} and {{q|He is men&shy;tally ill}}}}does not lie in any ob&shy;serv&shy;able ''facts'' to which they may point, but may con&shy;sist only of a dif&shy;fer&shy;ence in our ''at&shy;ti&shy;tudes'' toward our sub&shy;ject.}}<ref>{{w|T. S. Szasz|Thomas_Szasz}}, {{qq|Polit&shy;ics and Mental Health}}, {{w|''Amer&shy;ican Journal of Psy&shy;chi&shy;atry''|American_Journal_of_Psychiatry}}, No. 115 (1958) (quoted by {{w|Erving Goffman|Erving_Goffman}} in {{w|''Asylums''|Asylums_(book)}}, p. 509).</ref> What sort of be&shy;ha&shy;viour is likely to lead those with the ap&shy;propri&shy;ate at&shy;ti&shy;tudes to see signs of mental ill&shy;ness and to set going the trans&shy;fer pro&shy;cess from {{p|358}}{{qq|person to pa&shy;tient}}? {{qq|Ordin&shy;arily the patho&shy;logy which first draws at&shy;ten&shy;tion to the pa&shy;tient{{s}} con&shy;di&shy;tion is con&shy;duct that is {{q|in&shy;ap&shy;propri&shy;ate in the situ&shy;a&shy;tion}}. &hellip; Further, since in&shy;ap&shy;propri&shy;ate beha&shy;viour is typic&shy;ally beha&shy;viour that some&shy;one does not like and finds ex&shy;tremely trouble&shy;some, deci&shy;sions con&shy;cern&shy;ing it tend to be polit&shy;ical, in the sense of ex&shy;pres&shy;sing the spe&shy;cial inter&shy;ests of some par&shy;tic&shy;u&shy;lar fac&shy;tion or person. &hellip;}}<ref>{{w|Erving Goffman|Erving_Goffman}}, ''{{w|Asylums{{dash}}Essays on the So&shy;cial Situ&shy;a&shy;tion of Mental Pa&shy;tients and Other In&shy;mates|Asylums_(book)}}'', New York, Anchor Books, 1961, pp. 363-4.</ref> As an ex&shy;ample of {{qq|in&shy;ap&shy;propri&shy;ate beha&shy;viour}}, con&shy;sider the case of {{qq|The Naked Prisoner}} ({{sc|{{w|freedom|Freedom_(newspaper)}}}}, 16.10.65). Mr. Paul Pawlowski was ar&shy;rested during a demon&shy;stra&shy;tion at the {{w|Spanish Embassy|Embassy_of_Spain,_London}} in {{w|London}}. Eventu&shy;ally reach&shy;ing {{w|Brixton Prison|HM_Prison_Brixton}}, he re&shy;fused to put on the stand&shy;ard pris&shy;on&shy;er{{s|r}} uni&shy;form and was con&shy;sequently locked up, naked, in his cell. Thus he re&shy;mained for ten days. On the tenth day he was inter&shy;viewed by a so&shy;cial worker: {{qq|&hellip; You know that two doctors have seen you while you have been in Brixton &hellip; they came to the con&shy;clu&shy;sion that what you need is a little stay in a mental hos&shy;pital.}} In fact he did not have the benefit of this con&shy;fine&shy;ment. The hos&shy;pital psy&shy;chi&shy;atrist de&shy;cided that Mr. Pawlowski{{s}} opin&shy;ions were not those of the ma&shy;jor&shy;ity but {{qq|people are not put into mental hos&shy;pitals for their opin&shy;ions. They do that sort of thing in {{w|Russia|Soviet_Union}}.}}{{ref|aster3|***}} Mr. Pawlowski was for&shy;tun&shy;ate in his psy&shy;chi&shy;atrist, but it is inter&shy;est&shy;ing to see how the pre{{-}}exist&shy;ing at&shy;ti&shy;tudes of offi&shy;cials brought him to the brink of ad&shy;mis&shy;sion. The overt polit&shy;ical im&shy;plica&shy;tions may make this ex&shy;ample ex&shy;cep&shy;tional{{dash|but it would not seem to be to the ad&shy;vant&shy;age of a person sus&shy;pected of mental ill&shy;ness to have been {{qq|mixed up in polit&shy;ics}} or {{qq|the dregs of so&shy;ciety in {{w|CND|Campaign_for_Nuclear_Disarmament}}}}}}which it seems, may well be taken as a con&shy;firm&shy;atory symp&shy;tom.{{ref|dagger|&dagger;}} The mental health service{{dash|like the edu&shy;ca&shy;tion {{qq|service}}}}is a func&shy;tional part of the present so&shy;cial system and, as such, acts to pre&shy;serve that system and its values. {{qq|The psy&shy;chi&shy;atric pro&shy;fes&shy;sion is a bureau&shy;cracy,}} writes James Green, a con&shy;trib&shy;utor to ''{{l|Views|https://lccn.loc.gov/sf83002178}}'', No. 8, {{qq|making an es&shy;sen&shy;tial con&shy;trib&shy;u&shy;tion to the run&shy;ning of gov&shy;ern&shy;ment and ad&shy;minis&shy;tra&shy;tion. &hellip; Most psy&shy;chi&shy;atrists would prob&shy;ably take for granted the struc&shy;ture and values of their own so&shy;ciety, in such a way that the thera&shy;peutic pro&shy;cess becomes a ques&shy;tion of re&shy;turn&shy;ing the sick person to his so&shy;cial con&shy;text or roles, e.g. his family, whether the con&shy;text and roles are them&shy;selves satis&shy;fact&shy;ory.}} Al&shy;though no doubt un&shy;repre&shy;sent&shy;at&shy;ive and redol&shy;ent of {{qq|what they do in Russia}} I can&shy;not resist quot&shy;ing the words of a psy&shy;chi&shy;atrist par&shy;ti&shy;cipant in a re&shy;cently tele&shy;vised dis&shy;cus&shy;sion: {{qq|Our func&shy;tion is to get people well enough to be in&shy;doc&shy;trin&shy;ated.}} It would be mis&shy;lead&shy;ing to sug&shy;gest that any&shy;thing but a tiny minor&shy;ity become in&shy;mates of asylums simply or only because they hold dis&shy;ap&shy;proved {{p|359}}opin&shy;ions, but pos&shy;sibly such cases may lead to a con&shy;sider&shy;a&shy;tion of the far more subtle {{qq|polit&shy;ical}} and so&shy;cial mean&shy;ing of the label&shy;ling and con&shy;fine&shy;ment of the un&shy;vocal ma&shy;jor&shy;ity.
  
  
Line 57: Line 57:
  
  
{{tab}}{{qq|Many of us, for quite some time have con&shy;sidered that prob&shy;lems of pun&shy;ish&shy;ment and re&shy;pres&shy;sion are most acute in the con&shy;text of im&shy;prison&shy;ment. But this is not so; the ''really'' in&shy;tract&shy;able prob&shy;lem in this sphere is that of the mental hos&shy;pital.}}
+
{{tab}}{{qq|Many of us, for quite some time have con&shy;sidered that prob&shy;lems of pun&shy;ish&shy;ment and re&shy;pres&shy;sion are most acute in the con&shy;text of im&shy;prison&shy;ment. But this is not so; the ''really'' in&shy;tract&shy;able pr&shy;ob&shy;lem in this sphere is that of the mental hos&shy;pital.}}
  
 
{{r|Roger Moody: {{qq|Driving The Mad In&shy;sane}}, {{w|''Peace News''|Peace_News}} ({{popup|3.6.66|3 June 1966}}).}}
 
{{r|Roger Moody: {{qq|Driving The Mad In&shy;sane}}, {{w|''Peace News''|Peace_News}} ({{popup|3.6.66|3 June 1966}}).}}
Line 66: Line 66:
 
{{tab}}Goffman states that only a small number of pa&shy;tients enter mental hos&shy;pital will&shy;ingly, in the sense that they believe it will be good for them, having come to see them&shy;selves as {{qq|men&shy;tally un&shy;bal&shy;anced}}{{dash}}and as Laing and Cooper argue, even in these cases this self{{-}}per&shy;cep&shy;tion as being {{qq|ill}} or {{qq|mad}} can be in&shy;duced by the beha&shy;viour or strat&shy;egy of the person{{s}} im&shy;medi&shy;ate relat&shy;ives and con&shy;tacts. The sequence from {{qq|person to pa&shy;tient}} can follow a series of as&shy;so&shy;ci&shy;ated stages set in mo&shy;tion by a {{qq|com&shy;plain&shy;ant}} who sees an action on the part of the pre{{-}}pa&shy;tient as per&shy;haps a {{qq|last{{-}}straw}} and re&shy;fers him to a suc&shy;ces&shy;sion of {{qq|medi&shy;ators}}{{dash|prob&shy;ably drawn from among teach&shy;ers, so&shy;cial workers, clergy, psych&shy;iatrists, law&shy;yers, po&shy;lice}}one of whom, with co{{-}}opera&shy;tion from the {{qq|sick}} man{{s}} relat&shy;ives, will com&shy;mit the indi&shy;vidual to hos&shy;pital with legal sanc&shy;tion. {{qq|The so&shy;ciety{{s}} offi&shy;cial view,}} writes Goffman, {{qq|is that in&shy;mates are there because they are suf&shy;fer&shy;ing from mental ill&shy;ness. However, in the degree that the {{q|men&shy;tally ill}} out&shy;side hos&shy;pitals numer&shy;ically ap&shy;proach or sur&shy;pass those inside hos&shy;pitals, one could say that mental pa&shy;tients dis&shy;tinct&shy;ively suf&shy;fer not from mental ill&shy;ness, but from con&shy;tin&shy;gen&shy;cies.}}<ref>ibid., p. 135.</ref> In other words, good or bad luck{{dash}}de&shy;pend&shy;ing on your point of view. One might debate the degree to which this whole pro&shy;cess is {{qq|volun&shy;tary}}{{dash}}bear&shy;ing in mind that the indi&shy;vidual is un&shy;pre&shy;pared for the nature of his future life in the hos&shy;pital, is prob&shy;ably living {{p|360}}in so&shy;cially dis&shy;tres&shy;sing circum&shy;stances which would have the ef&shy;fect of making most al&shy;tern&shy;at&shy;ives seem favour&shy;able, and is sub&shy;ject to col&shy;lus&shy;ive pres&shy;sure from both relat&shy;ives and {{qq|medi&shy;ators}}.
 
{{tab}}Goffman states that only a small number of pa&shy;tients enter mental hos&shy;pital will&shy;ingly, in the sense that they believe it will be good for them, having come to see them&shy;selves as {{qq|men&shy;tally un&shy;bal&shy;anced}}{{dash}}and as Laing and Cooper argue, even in these cases this self{{-}}per&shy;cep&shy;tion as being {{qq|ill}} or {{qq|mad}} can be in&shy;duced by the beha&shy;viour or strat&shy;egy of the person{{s}} im&shy;medi&shy;ate relat&shy;ives and con&shy;tacts. The sequence from {{qq|person to pa&shy;tient}} can follow a series of as&shy;so&shy;ci&shy;ated stages set in mo&shy;tion by a {{qq|com&shy;plain&shy;ant}} who sees an action on the part of the pre{{-}}pa&shy;tient as per&shy;haps a {{qq|last{{-}}straw}} and re&shy;fers him to a suc&shy;ces&shy;sion of {{qq|medi&shy;ators}}{{dash|prob&shy;ably drawn from among teach&shy;ers, so&shy;cial workers, clergy, psych&shy;iatrists, law&shy;yers, po&shy;lice}}one of whom, with co{{-}}opera&shy;tion from the {{qq|sick}} man{{s}} relat&shy;ives, will com&shy;mit the indi&shy;vidual to hos&shy;pital with legal sanc&shy;tion. {{qq|The so&shy;ciety{{s}} offi&shy;cial view,}} writes Goffman, {{qq|is that in&shy;mates are there because they are suf&shy;fer&shy;ing from mental ill&shy;ness. However, in the degree that the {{q|men&shy;tally ill}} out&shy;side hos&shy;pitals numer&shy;ically ap&shy;proach or sur&shy;pass those inside hos&shy;pitals, one could say that mental pa&shy;tients dis&shy;tinct&shy;ively suf&shy;fer not from mental ill&shy;ness, but from con&shy;tin&shy;gen&shy;cies.}}<ref>ibid., p. 135.</ref> In other words, good or bad luck{{dash}}de&shy;pend&shy;ing on your point of view. One might debate the degree to which this whole pro&shy;cess is {{qq|volun&shy;tary}}{{dash}}bear&shy;ing in mind that the indi&shy;vidual is un&shy;pre&shy;pared for the nature of his future life in the hos&shy;pital, is prob&shy;ably living {{p|360}}in so&shy;cially dis&shy;tres&shy;sing circum&shy;stances which would have the ef&shy;fect of making most al&shy;tern&shy;at&shy;ives seem favour&shy;able, and is sub&shy;ject to col&shy;lus&shy;ive pres&shy;sure from both relat&shy;ives and {{qq|medi&shy;ators}}.
  
{{tab}}As {{w|Malatesta|Errico_Malatesta}} noted in his essay {{qq|{{l|Anarchy|http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/errico-malatesta-anarchy}}}}, {{qq|Organs and func&shy;tions are in&shy;separ&shy;able terms. Take from an organ its func&shy;tion, and either the organ will die, or the func&shy;tion will re&shy;in&shy;state itself.}} The ex&shy;ist&shy;ence of the mental hos&shy;pital is just&shy;ified by its func&shy;tion of curing the men&shy;tally ill. {{qq|The pa&shy;tient{{s}} pres&shy;ence in the hos&shy;pital is taken as ''{{popup|prima facie|sufficient until proven otherwise}}'' evid&shy;ence that he is men&shy;tally ill, since the hos&shy;pital&shy;iza&shy;tion of these per&shy;sons is what the in&shy;sti&shy;tu&shy;tion is for.}} A very com&shy;mon answer to a pa&shy;tient who claims he is sane is the state&shy;ment: {{qq|If you aren{{t}} sick you wouldn{{t}} be in the hos&shy;pital.}}<ref>ibid., p. 380.</ref> One con&shy;sequence of this for the person ini&shy;tiated into a {{qq|career}} as a mental pa&shy;tient is that his past life will be re&shy;struc&shy;tured in terms of a {{qq|case history}}{{dash|and he may be denied rights of pri&shy;vacy over what he pre&shy;vi&shy;ously re&shy;garded as {{qq|his own busi&shy;ness}}}}any facet of which may now pro&shy;vide evid&shy;ence of {{qq|symp&shy;toms}}.<ref>For a re&shy;con&shy;struc&shy;tion of a psy&shy;chi&shy;atric inter&shy;roga&shy;tion see {{qq|The Case Con&shy;fer&shy;ence}}, ''{{l|Views|https://lccn.loc.gov/sf83002178}}'', No. 11, Summer, 1966. {{w|Elias Canetti<!-- 'Elia Canetti' in original -->|Elias_Canetti}} has written that {{qq|ques&shy;tion&shy;ing is a for&shy;cible in&shy;tru&shy;sion. When used as an in&shy;stru&shy;ment of power, it is like a knife cut&shy;ting into the flesh of the vic&shy;tim. &hellip; The most blat&shy;ant tyranny is the one that asks the most ques&shy;tions}} ({{w|''Crowds and Power''|Crowds_and_Power}}, Gollancz, 1962).</ref> Once inside, the pa&shy;tient may find the in&shy;ternal organ&shy;isa&shy;tion of they asylum domin&shy;ated by a {{qq|ward system}} separ&shy;at&shy;ing pa&shy;tients off into {{qq|dis&shy;ease}} cat&shy;egor&shy;ies, the vari&shy;ous levels pro&shy;vid&shy;ing dif&shy;fer&shy;ent stand&shy;ards of ac&shy;com&shy;mod&shy;a&shy;tion, food and grounds{{-}}and{{-}}town {{qq|priv&shy;ileges}}, among other factors of import&shy;ance in the life of the pa&shy;tient. The ma&shy;terial and so&shy;cial pro&shy;vi&shy;sions on each ward level are offi&shy;cially those that are most ap&shy;propri&shy;ate to the mental con&shy;di&shy;tion of the pa&shy;tient. But whilst the system may be just&shy;ified by its par&shy;tis&shy;ans on these grounds, it has an un&shy;ac&shy;know&shy;leged func&shy;tion as an inmate{{-}}con&shy;trol&shy;ling device. There is a direct par&shy;al&shy;lel here with the al&shy;leged pur&shy;pose of the {{w|stream&shy;ing|Tracking_(education)}} system in schools; in&shy;vari&shy;ably de&shy;fended on the basis of its edu&shy;ca&shy;tional value yet actu&shy;ally opera&shy;ting in schools as an im&shy;port&shy;ant com&shy;pon&shy;ent of the dis&shy;ciplin&shy;ary system. And in asylums, as in schools, these {{qq|divide and rule}} dis&shy;ciplin&shy;ary strat&shy;egies have de&shy;veloped as the best method of {{qq|man&shy;age&shy;ment by a small staff of a large number of in&shy;volun&shy;tary in&shy;mates}}.
+
{{tab}}As {{w|Malatesta|Errico_Malatesta}} noted in his essay {{qq|{{l|Anarchy|http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/errico-malatesta-anarchy}}}}, {{qq|Organs and func&shy;tions are in&shy;separ&shy;able terms. Take from an organ its func&shy;tion, and either the organ will die, or the func&shy;tion will re&shy;in&shy;state itself.}} The ex&shy;ist&shy;ence of the mental hos&shy;pital is just&shy;ified by its func&shy;tion of curing the men&shy;tally ill. {{qq|The pa&shy;tient{{s}} pres&shy;ence in the hos&shy;pital is taken as ''{{popup|prima facie|sufficient until proven otherwise}}'' evid&shy;ence that he is men&shy;tally ill, since the hos&shy;pital&shy;iza&shy;tion of these per&shy;sons is what the in&shy;sti&shy;tu&shy;tion is for.}} A very com&shy;mon answer to a pa&shy;tient who claims he is sane is the state&shy;ment: {{qq|If you aren{{t}} sick you wouldn{{t}} be in the hos&shy;pital.}}<ref>ibid., p. 380.</ref> One con&shy;sequence of this for the person ini&shy;tiated into a {{qq|career}} as a mental pa&shy;tient is that his past life will be re&shy;struc&shy;tured in terms of a {{qq|case history}}{{dash|and he may be denied rights of pri&shy;vacy over what he pre&shy;vi&shy;ously re&shy;garded as {{qq|his own busi&shy;ness}}}}any facet of which may now pro&shy;vide evid&shy;ence of {{qq|symp&shy;toms}}.<ref>For a re&shy;con&shy;struc&shy;tion of a psy&shy;chi&shy;atric inter&shy;roga&shy;tion see {{qq|The Case Con&shy;fer&shy;ence}}, ''{{l|Views|https://lccn.loc.gov/sf83002178}}'', No. 11, Summer, 1966. {{w|Elias Canetti<!-&shy;- 'Elia Canetti' in original -->|Elias_Canetti}} has written that {{qq|ques&shy;tion&shy;ing is a for&shy;cible in&shy;tru&shy;sion. When used as an in&shy;stru&shy;ment of power, it is like a knife cut&shy;ting into the flesh of the vic&shy;tim. &hellip; The most blat&shy;ant tyranny is the one that asks the most ques&shy;tions}} ({{w|''Crowds and Power''|Crowds_and_Power}}, Gollancz, 1962).</ref> Once inside, the pa&shy;tient may find the in&shy;ternal organ&shy;isa&shy;tion of they asylum domin&shy;ated by a {{qq|ward system}} separ&shy;at&shy;ing pa&shy;tients off into {{qq|dis&shy;ease}} cat&shy;egor&shy;ies, the vari&shy;ous levels pro&shy;vid&shy;ing dif&shy;fer&shy;ent stand&shy;ards of ac&shy;com&shy;mod&shy;a&shy;tion, food and grounds{{-}}and{{-}}town {{qq|priv&shy;ileges}}, among other factors of import&shy;ance in the life of the pa&shy;tient. The ma&shy;terial and so&shy;cial pro&shy;vi&shy;sions on each ward level are offi&shy;cially those that are most ap&shy;propri&shy;ate to the mental con&shy;di&shy;tion of the pa&shy;tient. But whilst the system may be just&shy;ified by its par&shy;tis&shy;ans on these grounds, it has an un&shy;ac&shy;know&shy;leged func&shy;tion as an inmate{{-}}con&shy;trol&shy;ling device. There is a direct par&shy;al&shy;lel here with the al&shy;leged pur&shy;pose of the {{w|stream&shy;ing|Tracking_(education)}} system in schools; in&shy;vari&shy;ably de&shy;fended on the basis of its edu&shy;ca&shy;tional value yet actu&shy;ally opera&shy;ting in schools as an im&shy;port&shy;ant com&shy;pon&shy;ent of the dis&shy;ciplin&shy;ary system. And in asylums, as in schools, these {{qq|divide and rule}} dis&shy;ciplin&shy;ary strat&shy;egies have de&shy;veloped as the best method of {{qq|man&shy;age&shy;ment by a small staff of a large number of in&shy;volun&shy;tary in&shy;mates}}.
  
{{tab}}Because so&shy;ciety needs luna&shy;tics to pro&shy;vide it with re&shy;as&shy;sur&shy;ance of its own san&shy;ity, so it has need of in&shy;sti&shy;tu&shy;tions to con&shy;tain them. But as with prisons, the real enemy is not the ma&shy;terial struc&shy;ture{{dash|{{qq|It is our own anxi&shy;ety which forces us to lock people up}}<ref>A sen&shy;tence of Dr. Joshua Dierer{{s}}, speak&shy;ing at the {{w|World Federa&shy;tion of Mental Health|World_Federation_for_Mental_Health}}, 1960 (quoted by [[Author:Colin Ward|Colin Ward]] in {{qq|[[Anarchy 4/Where the shoe pinches|Where The Shoe Pinches]]}}, [[Anarchy 4|{{sc|anarchy}} 4]]).</ref>}}and it is through anxi&shy;ety about our own san&shy;ity that we build walls around the {{qq|men&shy;tally ill}}. {{qq|Mental hos&shy;pitals are not found in our so&shy;ciety because super&shy;visors, psych&shy;iatrists and at&shy;tend&shy;ants want jobs; mental hos&shy;pitals are found because there is a market for them. If all the mental hos&shy;pitals in a given region were emptied and closed down today, to&shy;morrow relat&shy;ives, po&shy;lice, and judges would raise a clamour for new ones; and these true clients of the mental hos&shy;pital would de&shy;mand an in&shy;sti&shy;tu&shy;tion to sat&shy;isfy their needs.}}<ref>Goffman, op. cit., p. 384.</ref>
+
{{tab}}Because so&shy;ciety needs luna&shy;tics to pro&shy;vide it with re&shy;as&shy;sur&shy;ance of its own san&shy;ity, so it has need of in&shy;sti&shy;tu&shy;tions to con&shy;tain them. But as with prisons, the real enemy is not the ma&shy;terial struc&shy;ture{{dash|{{qq|It is our own anxi&shy;ety which forces us to lock people up}}<ref>A sen&shy;tence of Dr. Joshua Dierer{{s}}, speak&shy;ing at the {{w|World Federa&shy;tion of Mental Health|World_Federation_for_Mental_Health}}, 1960 (quoted by [[Author:Colin Ward|Colin Ward]] in {{qq|[[Anarchy 4/Where the shoe pinches|Where The Shoe Pinches]]}}, [[Anarchy 4|{{sc|anarchy}} 4]]).</ref>}}and it is through anxi&shy;ety about our own san&shy;ity that we build walls around the {{qq|men&shy;tally ill}}. {{qq|Mental hos&shy;pitals are not found in our so&shy;ciety because super&shy;visors, psych&shy;iatrists and at&shy;tend&shy;ants want jobs; mental hos&shy;pitals are found because there is a market for them. If all the mental hos&shy;pitals in a given region were emptied and closed down today, to&shy;morrow relat&shy;ives, po&shy;lice, and judges would raise a clamour for new ones; and these true clients of the mental hos&shy;pital would de&shy;&shy;mand an in&shy;sti&shy;tu&shy;tion to sat&shy;isfy their needs.}}<ref>Goffman, op. cit., p. 384.</ref>
  
  
Line 94: Line 94:
  
  
'''THE FAMILY{{dash}}{{qq|FROM GOOD TO BAD TO MAD}}'''
+
{{p|s6}}'''THE FAMILY{{dash}}{{qq|FROM GOOD TO BAD TO MAD}}'''
  
  
Line 100: Line 100:
  
 
{{r|{{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}}: ''{{w|The Self and Others|Self_and_Others}}''.}}
 
{{r|{{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}}: ''{{w|The Self and Others|Self_and_Others}}''.}}
 +
 +
 +
{{tab}}Sartre holds that all groups are struc&shy;tured against an aware&shy;ness of a {{qq|spec&shy;tator}}. This {{qq|spec&shy;tator}} may be an indi&shy;vidual{{dash|as in the case of chil&shy;dren seeing them&shy;selves as {{qq|pupils}} in rela&shy;tion to a teacher}}or an&shy;other group, as in the case of workers con&shy;sti&shy;tu&shy;ting them&shy;selves against man&shy;agers. This spac&shy;tator he calls the {{qq|Third}} for whom the group ex&shy;ists as an object. Laing and Cooper seem to have de&shy;veloped their views on groups{{dash|and in par&shy;tic&shy;u&shy;lar, the family system of the future {{qq|schizo&shy;phrenic}}from Sartre{{s}} inter&shy;preta&shy;tion of group struc&shy;ture and cohe&shy;sion. In elab&shy;or&shy;at&shy;ing their theories the British ex&shy;isten&shy;tial ana&shy;lysts have made use of a number of terms, some of their own crea&shy;tion, whilst others are also used by Sartre. This rather tech&shy;nical and eso&shy;teric lan&shy;guage creates a dens&shy;ity in some of their writing which ob&shy;scures the im&shy;port&shy;ance of what is being said; in my view, the value of Laing and Cooper{{s}} book ''Reason and Viol&shy;ence'' is much re&shy;duced by their over{{-}}reli&shy;ance on such terms and it is a pity that what one senses to be im&shy;port&shy;ant ideas are couched in lan&shy;guage which re&shy;quires a good deal of de&shy;cipher&shy;ing before it becomes in&shy;tel&shy;ligible. If this par&shy;tic&shy;u&shy;lar book had been in ex&shy;ist&shy;ence at the time {{w|Orwell|George_Orwell}} was pre&shy;paring his essay {{qq|Polit&shy;ics and the English Lan&shy;guage}} it would have pro&shy;vided him with some re&shy;mark&shy;able cau&shy;tion&shy;ary ex&shy;tracts.
 +
 +
{{tab}}The British ex&shy;ist&shy;en&shy;tial&shy;ists make use of two words, series and nexus, in dif&shy;fer&shy;en&shy;ti&shy;ating between kinds of group{{dash}}and two words, praxis and pro&shy;cess, which de&shy;scribe group dy&shy;nam&shy;ics or the rela&shy;tion&shy;ships between group mem&shy;bers. A series is typic&shy;ally, a human as&shy;so&shy;ci&shy;a&shy;tion on negat&shy;ive grounds{{dash}}for ex&shy;ample a bus queue in which the sole link between per&shy;sons is a com&shy;mon desire to travel on the bus; each person in the queue being {{qq|one too many}} for the others. Also re&shy;garded as series are per&shy;sons united solely on the basis of op&shy;posi&shy;tion to some shared con&shy;cept: anti{{-}}semites sharing only their hatred of Jews, or one could per&shy;haps say anarch&shy;ists, united by shared op&shy;posi&shy;tion to the state (the only belief com&shy;mon to ''all'' anarch&shy;ist views). A series may move towards being a group through {{qq|an act of group{{-}}syn&shy;thesis}} (Laing{{s}} term). {{qq|If I think of cer&shy;tain others as together with me, and cer&shy;tain others as not together with me, I have already under&shy;taken two acts of syn&shy;thesis, re&shy;sult&shy;ing in ''we'' and ''them''. However, in order that ''we'' have a group iden&shy;tity, it is not enough that I re&shy;gard, let us say, you and him as con&shy;sti&shy;tu&shy;ting a ''we'' with myself. You and he have to per&shy;form sim&shy;ilar acts of syn&shy;thesis, each on his own behalf. In this ''we'' (me, and you, and him), each of ''us'' recog&shy;nises not only our own private syn&shy;theses, but also the syn&shy;theses that each of the others makes.}}<ref>{{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}}, {{qq|Us and Them}}, ''{{l|Views|https://lccn.loc.gov/sf83002178}},'' No. 11.</ref>
 +
 +
{{tab}}The dis&shy;tinct&shy;ive qual&shy;ities of the nexus are that each person ac&shy;know&shy;{{p|363}}ledges: the need of each for the others; the ex&shy;ist&shy;ence of strong bonds between mem&shy;bers (not main&shy;tained prin&shy;cip&shy;ally by in&shy;sti&shy;tu&shy;tional or organ&shy;isa&shy;tion struc&shy;tures, or a shared ex&shy;ternal {{qq|com&shy;mon ob&shy;ject}}. {{qq|The rela&shy;tion&shy;ships of per&shy;sons in a nexus are char&shy;ac&shy;ter&shy;ised by en&shy;dur&shy;ing and in&shy;tens&shy;ive face{{-}}to{{-}}face recip&shy;rocal in&shy;flu&shy;ence on each other{{s}} ex&shy;peri&shy;ence and beha&shy;viour.}}<ref>{{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}} and {{w|A. Esterson|Aaron_Esterson}}, {{popup|op. cit.|opere citato: cited above}}</ref> The family, or at least the family as we are ac&shy;cus&shy;tomed to think of it, is repre&shy;sent&shy;at&shy;ive of a nexus.
 +
 +
{{tab}}Praxis and pro&shy;cess are both terms used by Sartre. Basic&shy;ally, praxis is what is done by some&shy;one: {{qq|deeds done by doers}}, {{qq|the acts of an indi&shy;vidual or group}}; whilst pro&shy;cess re&shy;fers to {{qq|what just hap&shy;pens}}, activ&shy;ity not in&shy;tended by any&shy;one and of which no one person in a group may be aware.
 +
 +
{{tab}}The posi&shy;tion of the person within the group will af&shy;fect his idea of him&shy;self{{dash}}of who he is. In the same way his view of others in the group af&shy;fects their defin&shy;i&shy;tions of them&shy;selves. And again, his beha&shy;viour will be af&shy;fected by his idea of what other people make of him. As a person moves during even one day, from group to group, from one mode of as&shy;so&shy;ci&shy;a&shy;tion to an&shy;other, he must adapt him&shy;self to each con&shy;text: {{qq|Each group re&shy;quires more or less rad&shy;ical in&shy;ternal trans&shy;forma&shy;tion of the per&shy;sons who com&shy;prise it. Con&shy;sider the meta&shy;morph&shy;oses that the one man may go through in one day &hellip; family man, speck of crowd dust, func&shy;tion&shy;ary in the organ&shy;isa&shy;tion, friend. These are not simply dif&shy;fer&shy;ent roles: each is a whole past and present and future, of&shy;fer&shy;ing dif&shy;fer&shy;ing op&shy;tions and con&shy;straints, dif&shy;fer&shy;ent degrees of change or iner&shy;tia, dif&shy;fer&shy;ent kinds of close&shy;ness and dis&shy;tance, dif&shy;fer&shy;ent sets of rights and ob&shy;liga&shy;tions, dif&shy;fer&shy;ent pledges and pro&shy;mises.}}<ref>{{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}}, {{qq|Us and Them}}, {{popup|op. cit.|opere citato: cited above}}</ref>
 +
 +
{{tab}}Dr. Laing{{s}} second book ''{{w|The Self and Others|Self_and_Others}}'' deals with the way in which a person is af&shy;fected by his situ&shy;ation in a {{qq|nexus}} of others, in par&shy;tic&shy;u&shy;lar within the family. {{qq|The others either can con&shy;trib&shy;ute to the per&shy;son{{s}} self{{-}}ful&shy;fil&shy;ment, or they can be a potent factor in his losing him&shy;self (ali&shy;en&shy;a&shy;tion) even to the point of mad&shy;ness.}} He as&shy;serts his belief that {{qq|fantasy is a mode of ex&shy;peri&shy;ence}} and that rela&shy;tion&shy;ships on a fantasy level are {{qq|as basic to all human rela&shy;ted&shy;ness as the inter&shy;ac&shy;tions that most people most of the time are more aware of.}}
 +
 +
{{tab}}What hap&shy;pens in the fam&shy;il&shy;ies of {{qq|schizo&shy;phrenics}}? It is im&shy;port&shy;ant to em&shy;phas&shy;ise that it is not the thesis of these workers that the family rather than the indi&shy;vidual is {{qq|ill}}. A group is not an organ&shy;ism{{dash}}even though it may ap&shy;pear to be one to its mem&shy;bers or to ob&shy;servers out&shy;side it. A human group of what&shy;ever size, does not pos&shy;sess either a body or a mind that can be either well or ill. In the family, a per&shy;son{{s}} self can be either con&shy;firmed or dis&shy;con&shy;firmed by the actions and in&shy;flu&shy;ence{{dash|in&shy;clud&shy;ing in&shy;flu&shy;ence in {{qq|fantasy}}}}of others in the family nexus. Mysti&shy;fi&shy;ca&shy;tion of a person can be car&shy;ried so far that all genu&shy;ine ex&shy;pres&shy;sions of in&shy;depend&shy;ent de&shy;velop&shy;ment are denied valid&shy;ity. {{qq|in the fam&shy;il&shy;ies of schizo&shy;phrenic pa&shy;tients in&shy;ten&shy;tions, which link up with the {{q|psy&shy;chotic acts}} of the pa&shy;tient are denied, or even, their anti&shy;thesis as&shy;serted so that the pa&shy;tient{{s}} actions have the ap&shy;pear&shy;ance of pure pro&shy;cess un&shy;related to praxis and may even be ex&shy;peri&shy;enced by him as such.}}<ref>{{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}}, {{qq|Two Types of Ration&shy;ality}}, {{w|''New Left Review''|New_Left_Review}}, No. 29.</ref> In the moving final sec&shy;tion of ''The Divided Self'' (called {{qq|The Ghost of the Weed {{p|364}}Garden}}) R. D. Laing de&shy;scribes the clin&shy;ical bio&shy;graphy of a schizo&shy;phrenic. This was based on a series of inter&shy;views with the pa&shy;tient, mem&shy;bers of the pa&shy;tient{{s}} family, both indi&shy;vidu&shy;ally and jointly with other mem&shy;bers. These inter&shy;views were de&shy;signed to secure the in&shy;forma&shy;tion neces&shy;sary for an ex&shy;ist&shy;en&shy;tial ana&shy;lysis and were not a form of group psy&shy;cho&shy;ther&shy;apy. It is here that Laing first out&shy;lines the se&shy;quence which would ap&shy;pear to be typical of this kind of family inter&shy;ac&shy;tion: whilst each family mem&shy;ber had his or her own view of the pa&shy;tient{{-}}to{{-}}be{{s}} life, they all agreed on three basic phases:
 +
 +
# {{qq|The pa&shy;tient was a ''good'', normal, healthy child; until she gradu&shy;ally began|l}}
 +
# {{qq|to be ''bad'', to do or say things that caused great dis&shy;tress, and which were on the whole {{q|put down}} to naughti&shy;ness or bad&shy;ness, until|l}}
 +
# {{qq|this went beyond all toler&shy;able limits so that she could only be re&shy;garded as com&shy;pletely ''mad''.}}
 +
 +
What was seen by the mother as her daugh&shy;ter{{s}} {{qq|good}} period, in infancy and early child&shy;hood, she de&shy;scribed with such re&shy;marks as {{qq|she gave no trouble}}, {{qq|she always did what she was told}}. Laing com&shy;ments that what to the mother were signs of good&shy;ness, were signs that the child had never been per&shy;mit&shy;ted to become {{qq|ex&shy;ist&shy;en&shy;tially alive}}{{dash}}in fact {{qq|being ex&shy;ist&shy;en&shy;tially dead re&shy;ceives the high&shy;est com&shy;menda&shy;tion}}. The {{qq|bad}} period was the time of ad&shy;oles&shy;cence, during which the pa&shy;tient made her great&shy;est strug&shy;gle towards a real&shy;isa&shy;tion of her own self through auto&shy;nom&shy;ous action but found that her ef&shy;forts were con&shy;tinu&shy;ally de&shy;feated by {{qq|the com&shy;plete ab&shy;sence of any&shy;one in her world who could or would see some sense in her point of view}}. The trans&shy;fer from {{qq|bad}} to {{qq|mad}} came as some&shy;thing of a relief to the rest of the family, who {{qq|blamed them&shy;selves for not real&shy;ising sooner}}. As the mother said: {{qq|I knew she really could not have meant the awful things she said to me. In a way, I blame myself but, in a way, I{{m}} glad that it was an ill&shy;ness after all, but if only I had not waited so long before I took her to a doctor.}}
 +
 +
{{tab}}In ''San&shy;ity, Mad&shy;ness and the Family'' (the first volume of an un&shy;com&shy;pleted study) Drs. Laing and Esterson present ex&shy;tracts from inter&shy;views with mem&shy;bers of 11 fam&shy;il&shy;ies, all of which con&shy;tained daugh&shy;ters dia&shy;gnosed as {{qq|schizo&shy;phrenic}}. In the Intro&shy;duc&shy;tion to this book the authors write {{qq|&hellip; we believe that we show that the ex&shy;peri&shy;ence and beha&shy;viour of schizo&shy;phrenics is much more so&shy;cially intel&shy;li&shy;gible than has come to be sup&shy;posed by most psy&shy;chi&shy;atrists &hellip; we believe that the shift of point of view that these de&shy;scrip&shy;tions both em&shy;body and de&shy;mand has an histor&shy;ical sig&shy;ni&shy;fic&shy;ance no less rad&shy;ical than the shift from a demon&shy;o&shy;log&shy;ical to a clin&shy;ical view&shy;point 300 years ago.}} Beha&shy;viour which is eventu&shy;ally inter&shy;preted by the family as a sign of mad&shy;ness is, they argue, the out&shy;ward ex&shy;pres&shy;sion of a desper&shy;ate at&shy;tempt on the part of the {{qq|mad one}} to {{qq|make sense of a sense&shy;less situ&shy;ation}}{{dash|to pre&shy;serve some au&shy;then&shy;tic ele&shy;ments of per&shy;son&shy;ality}}a strug&shy;gle for auto&shy;nomy, spon&shy;tan&shy;eity, re&shy;spons&shy;ibil&shy;ity and {{qq|free&shy;dom}}. Here is an ex&shy;cerpt from Laing and Esterson{{s}} tran&shy;script of Mr. and Mrs. Gold{{s}} ac&shy;count of their daughter: {{qq|When she is her {{q|real}} self, that is, when she is {{q|well}}, she is not to be seri&shy;ously inter&shy;ested in writers or art, not to wear col&shy;oured stock&shy;ings, not to listen to jazz in a jazz club, not to bring friends home, not to stay out late. It is only from time to time that Ruth tries to as&shy;sert her&shy;self over against this par&shy;ental eternal es&shy;sence, and when she does she wears clothes to her liking, and in&shy;sists vehem&shy;ently on going where and with whom she wishes. Then her mother {{q|knows}} and {{q|at&shy;tack}} is coming on. She is told she is being dif&shy;fi&shy;cult, in&shy;con&shy;sider&shy;ate, dis&shy;re&shy;spect&shy;ful, thought&shy;less, because she is causing her parents such anxi&shy;ety{{dash}}but they do not blame or hold her re&shy;spons&shy;ible for all this, because they know she is odd and ill. Thus mys&shy;ti&shy;fied and put in an in&shy;toler&shy;able posi&shy;tion she becomes ex&shy;cited and desper&shy;ate, makes {{q|wild}} ac&shy;cus&shy;a&shy;tions that her parents do not want her to live, and runs out of the house. &hellip;}}<ref>{{popup|op. cit.|opere citato: cited above}}, p. 155.</ref>
 +
 +
{{tab}}These writers claim, and I think demon&shy;strate, that armed with a know&shy;ledge of the pa&shy;tient{{s}} ex&shy;ist&shy;en&shy;tial situ&shy;ation, it is pos&shy;sible to make sense of what {{qq|psy&shy;chi&shy;atrists still by and large re&shy;gard as non&shy;sense}}. For example, Julie, the pa&shy;tient in {{qq|The Ghost of the Weed Garden}} re&shy;ferred to her&shy;self whilst in her {{qq|psy&shy;chotic}} state as {{qq|Mrs. Taylor}} and as a {{qq|tolled bell}}. Dr. Laing inter&shy;prets her chosen title {{qq|Mrs. Taylor}} as ex&shy;pres&shy;sing the feel&shy;ings: {{qq|I{{m}} tailor made; I{{m}} a tailored maid; I was made, fed, clothed and tailored}} and a {{qq|tolled bell}} is also {{qq|the told belle}} {{qq|the girl who always did what she was told}}. The schizo&shy;phrenic{{s}} {{qq|delu&shy;sions}} of per&shy;secu&shy;tion are real ex&shy;pres&shy;sions of re&shy;ac&shy;tion in re&shy;sponse to real per&shy;secu&shy;tion and are ex&shy;ist&shy;en&shy;tially true; that is to say they are {{qq|liter&shy;ally true state&shy;ments within the terms of refer&shy;ence of the indi&shy;vidual who makes them.}}{{ref|dagger2|††}}
 +
 +
{{tab}}The person is now launched on a {{qq|career}} as a mental pa&shy;tient. He is con&shy;firmed in this role by so&shy;ciety{{s}} agents the psy&shy;chi&shy;atrists, in col&shy;lu&shy;sion with the pa&shy;tient{{s}} family, and by pro&shy;cess of be&shy;trayal and de&shy;grada&shy;tion<ref>{{w|Erving Goffman|Erving_Goffman}} in {{w|''Asylums''|Asylums_(book)}} makes use of the term {{qq|career}} to de&shy;note {{qq|the so&shy;cial strand}} of a per&shy;son{{s}} life in&shy;au&shy;gur&shy;ated at the moment of his defin&shy;i&shy;tion as a mental pa&shy;tient; {{qq|be&shy;trayal fun&shy;nel}} to de&shy;scribe the cir&shy;cuit of figures (relat&shy;ives, psy&shy;chi&shy;atrists, etc.) whose inter&shy;ac&shy;tions end with the pa&shy;tient{{s}} con&shy;fine&shy;ment in the {{p|374}}asylum, and {{qq|de&shy;grada&shy;tion ce&shy;re&shy;mo&shy;nial}} for the psy&shy;chi&shy;atric exam&shy;ina&shy;tion pre&shy;ced&shy;ing the pa&shy;tient{{s}} ad&shy;mis&shy;sion.</ref> becomes an in&shy;mate of a mental hos&shy;pital, which in&shy;sti&shy;tu&shy;tion em&shy;bodies {{qq|a so&shy;cial struc&shy;ture which in many re&shy;spects re&shy;du&shy;plic&shy;ates the mad&shy;den&shy;ing pecu&shy;li&shy;ar&shy;ities of the pa&shy;tient{{s}} family &hellip; he finds psy&shy;chi&shy;atrists, ad&shy;min&shy;is&shy;trat&shy;ors, nurses who are his verit&shy;able par&shy;ents, broth&shy;ers, sisters, who play an inter&shy;per&shy;sonal game which only too often re&shy;sembles in the in&shy;tric&shy;a&shy;cies of its rules the game he failed in at home.}}<ref>{{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}}, {{qq|Viol&shy;ence in Psy&shy;chi&shy;atry}}, {{popup|op. cit.|opere citato: cited above}}</ref>
 +
 +
{{tab}}The ex&shy;ist&shy;en&shy;tial ana&shy;lysts have as&shy;serted that a great deal of what passes for treat&shy;ment in mental in&shy;sti&shy;tu&shy;tions is viol&shy;ence. Per&shy;haps we can now begin to see what is meant by this. David Cooper in his art&shy;icle in ''Views,'' No. 8 quotes Sartre{{s}} defin&shy;i&shy;tion of viol&shy;ence: {{qq|The cor&shy;ros&shy;ive {{p|366}} action of the free&shy;dom of a person on the free&shy;dom of an&shy;other.}} And he ex&shy;plains this: {{qq|The action of a person &hellip; can de&shy;stroy the free&shy;dom of an&shy;other or at least para&shy;lyse it by mys&shy;ti&shy;fica&shy;tion.}} In an art&shy;icle printed in ''{{w|Peace News|Peace_News}}'' (22.1.65) called {{qq|Mas&shy;sacre of the In&shy;no&shy;cents}} R. D. Laing makes his under&shy;stand&shy;ing of the word clear: {{qq|Love and viol&shy;ence, pro&shy;perly speak&shy;ing, are polar op&shy;pos&shy;ites. Love lets the other be, but with af&shy;fec&shy;tion and con&shy;cern. Viol&shy;ence at&shy;tempts to con&shy;strain the other{{s}} free&shy;dom, to force him to act in the way we desire, but with ultim&shy;ate lack of con&shy;cern, with in&shy;dif&shy;fer&shy;ence to the other{{s}} own ex&shy;ist&shy;ence or des&shy;tiny.}} The basic theme of his art&shy;icle is that a most brutal and de&shy;struct&shy;ive form of viol&shy;ence is {{qq|viol&shy;ence mas&shy;quer&shy;ad&shy;ing as love}}. In rela&shy;tion to the family and its {{qq|schizo&shy;phrenic}} mem&shy;ber, action to secure care and at&shy;ten&shy;tion in hos&shy;pital for some&shy;one who is {{qq|ill}} could well be inter&shy;preted as an ex&shy;pres&shy;sion of con&shy;cern and love. Whether or not one believes that this pro&shy;cess and the pa&shy;tient{{s}} sub&shy;sequent treat&shy;ment is a form of viol&shy;ence will de&shy;pend in part, on whether one believes that there is any ill&shy;ness {{qq|in}} the person to be {{qq|cured}}. It is not viol&shy;ence to am&shy;pu&shy;tate a {{w|gan&shy;gren&shy;ous|Gangrene}} leg. We would all agree that it would be a viol&shy;ent pro&shy;ject to per&shy;suade a person that his leg was dis&shy;eased ({{qq|because you do not keep in step with us &hellip;}}), to find a sur&shy;geon who believes that there is a so&shy;cial need for one{{-}}legged people{{dash}}and for him to cut off the leg. In the actual case of the hos&shy;pital&shy;ised schizo&shy;phrenic each person in the chain sees himself as acting in the best inter&shy;ests of the others &hellip; {{qq|but we have also to re&shy;mem&shy;ber that good in&shy;ten&shy;tions and all the wrap&shy;pings of re&shy;spect&shy;abil&shy;ity very often cover a truly cruel human real&shy;ity.}}<ref>ibid.</ref>
 +
 +
 +
'''THEORIES IN PRACTICE: {{qq|THE ANTI-HOSPITAL}}
  
  
Line 110: Line 142:
 
{{note|aster3|***}}<!-- single asterisk in original --> This may be an al&shy;lu&shy;sion to a case which was re&shy;ceiv&shy;ing some pub&shy;li&shy;city at that time. Zenya Belov, a student, was con&shy;fined in a Russian mental in&shy;sti&shy;tu&shy;tion around Septem&shy;ber, 1965{{dash}}and he is pre&shy;sum&shy;ably still there. It was al&shy;leged that he had shown {{qq|schizo&shy;phrenic symp&shy;toms}} ({{qq|drawing dia&shy;grams, trying to re&shy;organ&shy;ise the world graph&shy;ic&shy;ally}}) but the only {{qq|symp&shy;toms}} evid&shy;ent to the British students who were with him shortly before the onset of {{qq|ill&shy;ness}} were his {{qq|un&shy;ortho&shy;dox and re&shy;form&shy;ist polit&shy;ical views}}.
 
{{note|aster3|***}}<!-- single asterisk in original --> This may be an al&shy;lu&shy;sion to a case which was re&shy;ceiv&shy;ing some pub&shy;li&shy;city at that time. Zenya Belov, a student, was con&shy;fined in a Russian mental in&shy;sti&shy;tu&shy;tion around Septem&shy;ber, 1965{{dash}}and he is pre&shy;sum&shy;ably still there. It was al&shy;leged that he had shown {{qq|schizo&shy;phrenic symp&shy;toms}} ({{qq|drawing dia&shy;grams, trying to re&shy;organ&shy;ise the world graph&shy;ic&shy;ally}}) but the only {{qq|symp&shy;toms}} evid&shy;ent to the British students who were with him shortly before the onset of {{qq|ill&shy;ness}} were his {{qq|un&shy;ortho&shy;dox and re&shy;form&shy;ist polit&shy;ical views}}.
  
{{note|dagger|&dagger;}} Refer&shy;ences to a letter from Brenda Jordan in ''{{w|Peace News|Peace_News}}'' (17.6.66).}}</font>
+
{{note|dagger|}} Refer&shy;ences to a letter from Brenda Jordan in ''{{w|Peace News|Peace_News}}'' (17.6.66).
 +
 
 +
{{note|2dagger|††}}<!-- single asterisk in original --> See also Laing{{s}} inter&shy;preta&shy;tion of the state&shy;ments of a schizo&shy;phrenic from the ori&shy;ginal ac&shy;count in {{w|Kraepelin|Emil_Kraepelin}}{{s}} {{l|''Lec&shy;tures on Clin&shy;ical Psy&shy;chi&shy;atry''|https://archive.org/details/lecturesonclini00kraegoog}}, 1905 (pp. 29-31 ''The Divided Self''). Laing writes: {{qq|What does this pa&shy;tient seem to be doing? Surely he is carry&shy;ing on a dia&shy;logue between his own par&shy;od&shy;ied ver&shy;sion of Kraepelin, and his own defi&shy;ant rebel&shy;ling self. {{q|You want to know that too? I tell you who is being meas&shy;ured and is meas&shy;ured and shall be meas&shy;ured. I know all that, and I could tell you, but I do not want to}}.}} Laing com&shy;ments: {{qq|This seems to be plain enough talk.}}
 +
}}</font>
  
  

Revision as of 20:34, 2 August 2017


353
Libertarian Psychiatry:
an introduction to
existential analysis

PETER FORD


s1
This art­icle aims to draw at­ten­tion to the work of a group of British psy­chi­atrists of whom the best known are R. D. Laing and David Cooper. They have achieved some no­tori­ety in this country because of the ex­tent of their di­ver­gence, both in theory and prac­tice, from cur­rent psy­chi­atric ortho­doxy—and par­tic­u­larly as a con­sequence of their refer­ences to the pre­val­ent “treat­ment” of the men­tally ill as “viol­ence”. As a teacher, I am not qual­ified to at­tempt more than an out­line of their ideas as under­stood by me, after read­ing their books and art­icles and some related studies. But the im­plica­tions of the work of the British ex­ist­en­tial­ist group ex­tend beyond the limits of psy­chi­atry—and the very gener­ality of their as­ser­tions in­vites a re­sponse from the layman. Writing of the pro­cess which in their view results in the ul­ti­mate in­val­id­a­tion of persons through the label­ling of them as “mad”, Laing asks: “… what func­tion does this pro­ced­ure serve for the civic order? These ques­tions are only begin­ning to be asked, much less answered. … So­cially, this work must now move to further under­stand­ing … of the mean­ing of all this within the larger con­text of the civic order of so­ciety—that is, of the polit­ical order, of the ways persons exer­cise control and power over one an­other.” (New Left Review, No. 28.) Anarch­ism is about just this, and any theory, from what­ever dis­cipline, which leads to a ques­tion­ing of the polit­ical order of so­ciety should have rel­ev­ance for us—and we should know some­thing about it.

  Dr. Laing has written that his main intel­lec­tual in­debt­ed­ness is to “the ex­ist­en­tial tradi­tion”—Kierke­gaard, Jaspers, Heideg­ger, Bins­wanger, Tillich and Sartreand of these there is no doubt that Sartre’s in­flu­ence has been the great­est. The British ana­lysts have clearly worked out their own the­or­et­ical basis and in many in­stan­ces have de­veloped Sartre’s ideas rather than merely adopted them as they stand. I am not cer­tain, for ex­ample how com­pletely Laing and Cooper share Sartre’s total re­jec­tion of the con­cept of “the un­con­scious”. However, their book Reason and Viol­ence: A Decade of Sartre’s Philo­sophy 1950-1960 (Tavistock, 1964) opens with a com­pli­ment­ary pre­fat­ory note from the French philo­sopher—I believe this is an un­usual honour for a book about his ideas—and this im­prim­atur sug­gests that what­ever their diver­gen­cies, they can­not be basic.

  In anarchy 44 J.-P. Sartre is re­ferred to as “one of the fore­most anarch­ist moral­ists” (Ian Vine: “The Moral­ity of Anarch­ism”). This de­scrip­tion com­pares in­triguingly with an­other, made by the so­cial­ist Alasdair MacIntyre, re­view­ing Sartre’s book The Prob­lem of Method in Peace News. He re­fers to Sartre as a newly found “spokes­man of genius” for “ersatz bolshev­iks” and “im­it­a­tion anarch­ists”. Not know­ing MacIntyre’s idea of the genu­ine art­icle, this does not ex­actly rule the French­man out and I believe his work may well just­ify a place on an anarch­ist’s book list. Writing with par­tic­u­lar refer­ence to Sartre’s recent work, MacIntyre notes that Sartre can offer no bonds, other than re­cip­roc­ally threat­ened viol­ence and terror, of suf­fi­cient strength to main­tain the co­he­sion of human groups in a world of “im­pos­sibly indi­vidual­ist indi­viduals”. Per­haps a spokes­man for Stirner­ites? Never­the­less, the poten­ti­alit­ies of Sartre’s philo­sophy as a basis for anarch­ism are in­cid­ental to my pur­pose here.

  The first of four epis­odes of this essay are in­tended to create a set­ting against which ex­ist­en­tial ana­lysis may be viewed.


s2
EXISTENTIAL FREEDOM


  “Man can­not be some­times slave and some­times free; he is wholly and forever free, or he is not free at all.”


  The con­cept of free­dom at the core of ex­ist­en­tial­ism is very dif­fer­ent from what I take to be the com­mon under­stand­ing of the term. In gen­eral usage, a man is free in as much as he can achieve his chosen ends with a min­imum of effort. Simil­arly, a man’s free­dom is re­duced as the ob­stacles between his de­sires and chosen ends are in­creased. Free­dom is re­garded as a measur­able quant­ity; one may have a lot or a little of it, and it can be taken away—or even “given”. The anarch­ist’s hypo­thet­ical destin­a­tion, the “free” so­ciety, may often be thought of in the sense of an har­mo­ni­ous envir­on­ment in which all re­mov­able ob­stacles between man’s de­sires and their ful­fil­ment have been elim­in­ated. But for Sartre, man is totally free by reason of his very being as man, and ob­stacles between de­sires and chosen ends are of no rel­ev­ance. To use a favoured ex­ist­en­tial­ist phrase, man is free by onto­lo­gical neces­sity. But his free­dom rests, within this con­cept, in his total re­spons­ibil­ity in the face of un­deter­mined choice and in his recog­ni­tion of the in­escap­able ob­lig­a­tion to choose. An intuit­ive aware­ness of this re­spons­ib­il­ity—per­haps pro­voked by some sort of “ex­treme situ­a­tion”—gives rise to what Sartre calls “the anguish of free­dom”. It is our fate to be free. “… One must always de­cide for one­self and efforts to shift the burden of re­spons­ib­il­ity upon others are neces­sar­ily self-de­feat­ing. Not to choose is also to choose, for even if we de­liver our power of de­ci­sion to others, we are still re­spons­ible for having done so. It is always the indi­vidual who de­cides that others will choose for him.”[1] In so far as we are free in our choices, we “create” the ob­stacles that lie between our pro­ject and its ful­fil­ment: “an in­sig­ni­fic­ant public of­fi­cial in Mont-de-Marsan without means may not have the op­por­tun­ity to go to New York if that be his ambi­tion. But the ob­stacles which stand in his way would not exist as ob­stacles were it not for his free choice and values: in this case, his desire to go
355
to New York.”[2] Even though human free­dom, in his view, is total, Sartre ad­mits of a sense in which it may be spoken of in terms of degree. A man may be said to become “more free” as his con­scious­ness of total free­dom and re­spons­ib­il­ity in­creases; and cer­tain situ­a­tions in life can crystal­lize this aware­ness. In an ap­par­ently cryptic para­graph in Being and No­thing­ness Sartre de­scribes the German Oc­cupa­tion of France during the last war as such a situ­a­tion. “… the choice that each of us made of his life and his being was an au­then­tic choice because it was made face to face with death, because it could always have been ex­pressed in these terms: ‘Rather death than …’.”[3] But the issue is not just one of an in­creased sense of re­spons­ib­il­ity for our day-to-day options—for in­stance in de­cid­ing upon a change in oc­cu­pa­tion, or merely which book to read next; most sig­ni­fic­antly we choose our­selves, and our day-to-day de­ci­sions neces­sarily re­flect this primary choice we have made. We are what we have chosen to be. All our sub­sequent modes of action are re­lated to this original “project-of-being”, “Freely chosen at the moment one wrenches one­self away from the in-itself to create one’s own world”[4] (the in-itself: the world of things). This event I take to be com­par­able with what R. D. Laing calls “ex­ist­en­tial birth” which, he sug­gests, is as essen­tial for a fully human ex­ist­ence as the bio­lo­gical birth which it nor­mally follows.* It is only in rela­tion to this funda­mental choice, the indi­vidual’s original “pro­ject-of-being” that his later beha­viour can be fully under­stood. The plaus­ibil­ity of this basic idea is not in­creased by Sartre’s denial of the divi­sion of the self into con­scious and un­con­scious modes; the idea of a tooth­less infant con­sciously de­termin­ing its future life­style and pur­pose is at first thought ab­surd. But whilst ex­pli­citly deny­ing valid­ity to the “un­con­scious” Sartre does separ­ate con­scious­ness into “re­flect­ive” and “non-re­flect­ive” levels, and it is at the non-re­flect­ive level that this funda­mental choice is made. He stresses that this original choice is in no way de­liber­ate: “This is not because it would be less con­scious or less ex­plicit than a de­liber­a­tion but, on the con­trary, because it is the found­a­tion of all de­liber­a­tion and because … a de­liber­a­tion re­quires an inter­pret­a­tion in terms of an original choice.”[5] The con­cepts of “au­then­ti­city” and its ap­proxim­ate op­po­site “bad-faith” are in a sense under­stand­able as judge­ments (al­though Sartre claims only to use these terms de­script­ively) upon the degree of con­cord­ance between the choices of our re­flect­ive con­scious­ness and our original pro­ject-of-being. In a pas­sage which bears di­rectly upon ex­ist­en­tial ana­lysis he writes that a man “can make vol­un­tary de­ci­sions which are op­posed to the funda­mental ends which he has chosen. These de­ci­sions can be only vol­un­tary—that is, re­flect­ive. … Thus, for ex­ample, I can de­cide to cure myself of stutter­ing. I can even
256
suc­ceed in it. … In fact I can ob­tain a result by using merely tech­nical methods. … But these re­sults will only dis­place the in­firm­ity from which I suf­fer; an­other will arise in its place and will in its own way ex­press the total end which I pur­sue. … It is the same with these cures as it is with the cure of hys­teria by elec­tric shock treat­ment. We know that this ther­apy can effect the dis­ap­pear­ance of an hys­terical con­trac­tion of the leg, but as one will see some time later the con­trac­tion will ap­pear in the arm. This is because the hys­teria can be cured only as a total­ity, for it is a total pro­ject of the for-itself”[6] (the for-itself: the world of con­scious­ness and in­ten­tion).

  Sartre argues against the Freud­ian three-way split of the per­sonal­ity into id, ego and super-ego and the Psycho-ana­lytic dictum of con­scious beha­viour as de­term­ined by drives, in­stincts and de­sires al­legedly eman­at­ing from the id. As Sartre’s argu­ments hinge upon his stated belief in man’s on­to­lo­gical free­dom, Freud’s pro­ject of “de­term­ina­tion by the un­con­scious” is met with similar ob­jec­tions to those made against other de­term­in­ist theories and I need not at­tempt to sum­mar­ise them here.[7] The only valid form of ther­apy is one aimed at dis­cover­ing an indi­vidual’s funda­mental pro­ject-of-being—and this is the pur­pose of ex­ist­en­tial ana­lysis (or psycho-ana­lysis; the pre­fix seems to be op­tional). “The prin­ciple of this psycho-ana­lysis is that man is a total­ity and not a col­lec­tion; he there­fore ex­presses him­self in his total­ity in the most in­sig­ni­fic­ant and the most super­fi­cial as­pects of his con­duct” (Being and No­thing­ness). Through the use of a tech­nique or method based on such as­sump­tions the ini­tially “crazy” actions of the in­sane may be made com­pre­hens­ible—and may even ap­pear “reason­able” if a picture of the world in which the pa­tient lives can be as­sembled.

  R. D. Laing has written that “only by the most out­rage­ous viol­a­tion of our­selves have we achieved our cap­ac­ity to live in relat­ive ad­just­ment to a civil­isa­tion ap­par­ently driven to its own de­struc­tion” and has de­scribed the “normal” person in the present age as “a half-crazed creature, more or less ad­justed to a mad world”.[8] What is the norm that gives the gen­erally ac­cepted mean­ing to such relat­ive de­scrip­tions as “mad”, “insane”, “mal­ad­justed”? And what is the sig­ni­fic­ance of what is done to the people that are dis­qual­i­fied when meas­ured against this cri­terion; the people that the mad offi­cials label as “offi­cially mad”?


s3
THE INSANE IN A MAD WORLD


  “In the con­text of our present mad­ness that we call normal­ity, san­ity, free­dom, all our frames of refer­ence are am­bigu­ous and equi­vocal.”

R. D. Laing: The Divided Self.


  In 1965 there were 160,000 people in mental hos­pitals in Britain and an estim­ated 200,000 psy­chotics in the com­mun­ity. Nearly half of all hos­pital beds are oc­cu­pied my the men­tally ill. In a tele­vision pro­gramme on mental health[9] the number of men­tally ill in Britain was given as half a million. The tele­vised psy­chi­atrist sug­gested that there were four main cat­egor­ies of ill­ness: people with mental de­form­ity,
357
old people with “mental equip­ment in de­cline” (… per­haps old people with no­where else to go?**), people with physiolo­gic­ally normal mental equip­ment but with ac­quired neur­otic pat­terns, and lastly, vic­tims of “bio-​chem­ical ill­ness”—in his words, “Struck down out of the blue”. The fourth cat­egory per­haps re­flects, more than any­thing else, the cur­rently fa­voured styles of treat­ment!

  By far the largest group is the third—the “neur­otics and psychot­ics”. Among these “schizo­phrenia” is the most common dia­gnosis. “In most European coun­tries about one per cent of the popu­la­tion go to hos­pital at least once in their life­time with the dia­gnosis schizo­phrenia.”[10] But what mean­ing can be given to these stat­istics and as­sess­ments without a stand­ard of san­ity or mad­ness? “Defin­i­tions of mental health pro­pounded by the ex­perts usually re­duce to the no­tion of con­form­ism, to a set of more or less ar­bit­rar­ily pos­ited so­cial norms. …”[11] The label­ling of people as mad can have the so­cial func­tion of defin­ing the area of “san­ity”—per­haps there is a par­al­lel with Durkheim’s theory of crime and pun­­ish­ment as “neces­sary” to re­spect­able so­ciety to mark off the limits of per­mis­sible and toler­ated beha­viour. “So­ciety needs lun­at­ics in order that it may regard itself as sane.”[12] It could also be argued that cer­tain kinds of so­ciety “need” lun­at­ics as their man­agers; a dis­cus­sion in Peace News re­cently was con­cerned with the un­certi­fi­able mad­ness of the Amer­ican Presid­ent in rela­tion to a “col­lect­ive norm of in­san­ity”. A Cor­re­spond­ent noted: “No sig­ni­fic­ant mem­ber of a power estab­lish­ment can ever be ‘cert­ifi­ably in­sane’ since it is this same estab­lish­ment which de­ter­mines the defin­i­tions of ‘san­ity’ and ‘in­san­ity’ and which de­cides—checked only by the oc­ca­sional con­science of an oc­ca­sional pro­fes­sional medi­cal man—when “in­san­ity” becomes “cert­ifi­able”.”[13]

  In offi­cial stat­istics there must, in any case, be a murky over­lap area between what comes out as “crime” and what as “lunacy”—and a lot of luck in who ends up in which in­stitu­tion. Per­haps it is the in­stitu­tional bureau­cracy that has most need of the labels: “Ac­cord­ing to the common­sense defin­i­tion,” writes Dr. Theodore Szasz, “mental health is the abil­ity to play what­ever the game of so­cial living might con­sist of and to play it well. Con­versely, to re­fuse to play, or to play badly, means that the person is men­tally ill. The ques­tion may now be raised as to what are the dif­fer­ences, if any between so­cial non­con­form­ity (or devi­a­tion) and mental ill­ness. Leaving tech­nical psy­chi­atric con­sider­a­tions aside for the moment, I shall argue that the dif­fer­ence between these two no&sh­y;tions—as ex­pressed for ex­ample by the state­ments ‘He is wrong’ and ‘He is men­tally ill’—does not lie in any ob­serv­able facts to which they may point, but may con­sist only of a dif­fer­ence in our at­ti­tudes toward our sub­ject.”[14] What sort of be­ha­viour is likely to lead those with the ap­propri­ate at­ti­tudes to see signs of mental ill­ness and to set going the trans­fer pro­cess from
358
“person to pa­tient”? “Ordin­arily the patho­logy which first draws at­ten­tion to the pa­tient’s con­di­tion is con­duct that is ‘in­ap­propri­ate in the situ­a­tion’. … Further, since in­ap­propri­ate beha­viour is typic­ally beha­viour that some­one does not like and finds ex­tremely trouble­some, deci­sions con­cern­ing it tend to be polit­ical, in the sense of ex­pres­sing the spe­cial inter­ests of some par­tic­u­lar fac­tion or person. …”[15] As an ex­ample of “in­ap­propri­ate beha­viour”, con­sider the case of “The Naked Prisoner” (freedom, 16.10.65). Mr. Paul Pawlowski was ar­rested during a demon­stra­tion at the Spanish Embassy in London. Eventu­ally reach­ing Brixton Prison, he re­fused to put on the stand­ard pris­on­ers’ uni­form and was con­sequently locked up, naked, in his cell. Thus he re­mained for ten days. On the tenth day he was inter­viewed by a so­cial worker: “… You know that two doctors have seen you while you have been in Brixton … they came to the con­clu­sion that what you need is a little stay in a mental hos­pital.” In fact he did not have the benefit of this con­fine­ment. The hos­pital psy­chi­atrist de­cided that Mr. Pawlowski’s opin­ions were not those of the ma­jor­ity but “people are not put into mental hos­pitals for their opin­ions. They do that sort of thing in Russia.”*** Mr. Pawlowski was for­tun­ate in his psy­chi­atrist, but it is inter­est­ing to see how the pre-​exist­ing at­ti­tudes of offi­cials brought him to the brink of ad­mis­sion. The overt polit­ical im­plica­tions may make this ex­ample ex­cep­tional—but it would not seem to be to the ad­vant­age of a person sus­pected of mental ill­ness to have been “mixed up in polit­ics” or “the dregs of so­ciety in CND”—which it seems, may well be taken as a con­firm­atory symp­tom. The mental health service—like the edu­ca­tion “service”—is a func­tional part of the present so­cial system and, as such, acts to pre­serve that system and its values. “The psy­chi­atric pro­fes­sion is a bureau­cracy,” writes James Green, a con­trib­utor to Views, No. 8, “making an es­sen­tial con­trib­u­tion to the run­ning of gov­ern­ment and ad­minis­tra­tion. … Most psy­chi­atrists would prob­ably take for granted the struc­ture and values of their own so­ciety, in such a way that the thera­peutic pro­cess becomes a ques­tion of re­turn­ing the sick person to his so­cial con­text or roles, e.g. his family, whether the con­text and roles are them­selves satis­fact­ory.” Al­though no doubt un­repre­sent­at­ive and redol­ent of “what they do in Russia” I can­not resist quot­ing the words of a psy­chi­atrist par­ti­cipant in a re­cently tele­vised dis­cus­sion: “Our func­tion is to get people well enough to be in­doc­trin­ated.” It would be mis­lead­ing to sug­gest that any­thing but a tiny minor­ity become in­mates of asylums simply or only because they hold dis­ap­proved
359
opin­ions, but pos­sibly such cases may lead to a con­sider­a­tion of the far more subtle “polit­ical” and so­cial mean­ing of the label­ling and con­fine­ment of the un­vocal ma­jor­ity.


s4
CURATIVE—OR PUNITIVE?


  “Many of us, for quite some time have con­sidered that prob­lems of pun­ish­ment and re­pres­sion are most acute in the con­text of im­prison­ment. But this is not so; the really in­tract­able pr­ob­lem in this sphere is that of the mental hos­pital.”

Roger Moody: “Driving The Mad In­sane”, Peace News (3.6.66).


  In his ac­count of “de-​in­sti­tu­tion­al­isa­tion” (anarchy 4) Colin Ward re­ferred to the prison as “the most sin­is­ter of in­sti­tu­tions” and no doubt it is. But as anarch­ists are aware, the state can make skil­ful use of the “ap­proved” con­cepts of crime and crim­in­ality to di­vert at­ten­tion from its own more grandi­ose but identical activ­it­ies: so we should be alert to the pos­si­bil­ity that the in­sti­tu­tions openly la­belled as prisons are not the only ones serving that func­tion. Sup­pose, as Roger Moody says in his art­icle that mental hos­pital and prison are “dif­fer­ent terms for the same thing”? If there is some truth in this there is con­sequently an ad­di­tional danger in that any­thing called a “hos­pital” has auto­mat­ic­ally a pro­tect­ive cocoon around it as a result of its claim to pro­vide ther­apy. But surely the “volun­tary” presence of many of the pa­tients in mental hos­pitals en­sures that they can­not have a pun­it­ive char­acter or ef­fect? A dif­fer­ent ap­proach is sug­gested by the Amer­ican so­ci­olo­gist Erving Goffman: “… We must see the mental hos­pital, in the re­cent histor­ical con­text in which it de­veloped, as one among a net­work of in­sti­tu­tions de­signed to pro­vide a res­id­ence for vari­ous cat­egor­ies of so­cially trouble­some people.”[16]

  Goffman states that only a small number of pa­tients enter mental hos­pital will­ingly, in the sense that they believe it will be good for them, having come to see them­selves as “men­tally un­bal­anced”—and as Laing and Cooper argue, even in these cases this self-​per­cep­tion as being “ill” or “mad” can be in­duced by the beha­viour or strat­egy of the person’s im­medi­ate relat­ives and con­tacts. The sequence from “person to pa­tient” can follow a series of as­so­ci­ated stages set in mo­tion by a “com­plain­ant” who sees an action on the part of the pre-​pa­tient as per­haps a “last-​straw” and re­fers him to a suc­ces­sion of “medi­ators”—prob­ably drawn from among teach­ers, so­cial workers, clergy, psych­iatrists, law­yers, po­lice—one of whom, with co-​opera­tion from the “sick” man’s relat­ives, will com­mit the indi­vidual to hos­pital with legal sanc­tion. “The so­ciety’s offi­cial view,” writes Goffman, “is that in­mates are there because they are suf­fer­ing from mental ill­ness. However, in the degree that the ‘men­tally ill’ out­side hos­pitals numer­ically ap­proach or sur­pass those inside hos­pitals, one could say that mental pa­tients dis­tinct­ively suf­fer not from mental ill­ness, but from con­tin­gen­cies.”[17] In other words, good or bad luck—de­pend­ing on your point of view. One might debate the degree to which this whole pro­cess is “volun­tary”—bear­ing in mind that the indi­vidual is un­pre­pared for the nature of his future life in the hos­pital, is prob­ably living
360
in so­cially dis­tres­sing circum­stances which would have the ef­fect of making most al­tern­at­ives seem favour­able, and is sub­ject to col­lus­ive pres­sure from both relat­ives and “medi­ators”.

  As Malatesta noted in his essay “Anarchy”, “Organs and func­tions are in­separ­able terms. Take from an organ its func­tion, and either the organ will die, or the func­tion will re­in­state itself.” The ex­ist­ence of the mental hos­pital is just­ified by its func­tion of curing the men­tally ill. “The pa­tient’s pres­ence in the hos­pital is taken as prima facie evid­ence that he is men­tally ill, since the hos­pital­iza­tion of these per­sons is what the in­sti­tu­tion is for.” A very com­mon answer to a pa­tient who claims he is sane is the state­ment: “If you aren’t sick you wouldn’t be in the hos­pital.”[18] One con­sequence of this for the person ini­tiated into a “career” as a mental pa­tient is that his past life will be re­struc­tured in terms of a “case history”—and he may be denied rights of pri­vacy over what he pre­vi­ously re­garded as “his own busi­ness”—any facet of which may now pro­vide evid­ence of “symp­toms”.[19] Once inside, the pa­tient may find the in­ternal organ­isa­tion of they asylum domin­ated by a “ward system” separ­at­ing pa­tients off into “dis­ease” cat­egor­ies, the vari­ous levels pro­vid­ing dif­fer­ent stand­ards of ac­com­mod­a­tion, food and grounds-​and-​town “priv­ileges”, among other factors of import­ance in the life of the pa­tient. The ma­terial and so­cial pro­vi­sions on each ward level are offi­cially those that are most ap­propri­ate to the mental con­di­tion of the pa­tient. But whilst the system may be just­ified by its par­tis­ans on these grounds, it has an un­ac­know­leged func­tion as an inmate-​con­trol­ling device. There is a direct par­al­lel here with the al­leged pur­pose of the stream­ing system in schools; in­vari­ably de­fended on the basis of its edu­ca­tional value yet actu­ally opera­ting in schools as an im­port­ant com­pon­ent of the dis­ciplin­ary system. And in asylums, as in schools, these “divide and rule” dis­ciplin­ary strat­egies have de­veloped as the best method of “man­age­ment by a small staff of a large number of in­volun­tary in­mates”.

  Because so­ciety needs luna­tics to pro­vide it with re­as­sur­ance of its own san­ity, so it has need of in­sti­tu­tions to con­tain them. But as with prisons, the real enemy is not the ma­terial struc­ture—“It is our own anxi­ety which forces us to lock people up”[20]and it is through anxi­ety about our own san­ity that we build walls around the “men­tally ill”. “Mental hos­pitals are not found in our so­ciety because super­visors, psych­iatrists and at­tend­ants want jobs; mental hos­pitals are found because there is a market for them. If all the mental hos­pitals in a given region were emptied and closed down today, to­morrow relat­ives, po­lice, and judges would raise a clamour for new ones; and these true clients of the mental hos­pital would de­­mand an in­sti­tu­tion to sat­isfy their needs.”[21]


s5
SCHIZOPHRENIA—A PSEUDO-​DISEASE?


  “In the popular mind the schizo­phrenic is the proto-​typical mad­man—author of the totally gra­tu­it­ous crazy act that always has over­tones of viol­ence to others”

David Cooper: Viol­ence in Psychiatry.


361
  The vari­ous titles given to mental dis­eases, says Goffman, serve to meet the needs of hos­pital census regu­la­tions. “When pressed … staff will allow that these syn­drome titles are vague and doubt­ful.” A lot of people at the present time, ap­pear to have schizo­phrenia—this dia­gnosis is ap­plied to two out of three pa­tients in British mental hos­pitals and it has been estim­ated that for every “schizo­phrenic” re­ceiv­ing some form of treat­ment there are ten “un­detec­ted” in the com­mun­ity.[22]

  One psycho-​ana­lytic view is that schizo­phrenia is the out­come of a split between a person’s “con­scious” and “sub­con­scious” forces which in the normal state are believed to work sim­ul­tan­eously. An­other idea—in schizo­phrenia “there is a subtle change in brain chem­istry which inter­feres in some way with nerve im­pulses.”[23] The pop­ular­ity of this view and others sim­ilar to it has led to an em­phasis on sur­gical or phys­ical treat­ment such as electro-​con­vuls­ive ther­apy (a low voltage shock passed between the temples) and, in some cases, opera­tions on the brain (leu­co­tomy and lo­botomy). In at least one London hos­pital schizo­phrenics have been placed in a deep freeze. Drugs are much used. And it seems that what are taken to be the symp­toms of the dis­ease can be elim­in­ated by the use of such means at least for a time. As Sartre ob­served, one “can ob­tain a result by using merely tech­nical methods.” But, as the writer of a sur­vey in The Ob­server (5.6.66) com­mented: “No one knows, ex­cept in the fuzzi­est out­line, what the treat­ments do. And none of them is a cure.” John Linsie in his article in anarchy 24 pointed out that the ef­fect­ive­ness of drugs and E.C.T. in tem­por­arily re­moving “symp­toms” has per­haps pre­vented more wide­spread re­search into the basic aeti­ology of the “dis­ease”. Schizo­phrenia often oc­curs within the same family and some re­search­ers believe that it is trans­mitted ge­net­ic­ally. John Linsie quoted Mayer-​Gross: “It may now be re­garded as estab­lished that hered­it­ary factors play a pre­domin­ant role in the causa­tion of schizo­phrenic psy­cho­sis”—and then trumped this with the opinion of an­other expert, Roth: “No simple ge­netic hypo­thesis ac­cords with all the facts.”

  This I hope is enough to pro­vide some basis for R. D. Laing’s and A. Esterson’s state­ment in the intro­duc­tion to San­ity, Mad­ness and the Family that there is no more dis­puted condi­tion in the whole field of medi­cine. “The one thing cer­tain about schizo­phrenia is that it is a dia­gnosis, that is a clin­ical label, ap­plied by some people to others.”[24] The es­sen­tially so­cial pro­cess which results ul­tim­ately in the fixing of this label to one person is the under­lying theme of three books and a good many articles by Dr. Laing and his col­leagues. I shall try to out­line their ac­count of this pro­cess sub­sequently, but an idea of their truly rad­ical con­clu­sions can be given here:

  “We do not use the term ‘schizo­phrenia’ to de­note any iden­ti­fi­able condi­tion which we believe exists ‘in’ one person.”[25]

  “I do not myself believe that there is any such ‘condi­tion’ as schizo­phrenia. …”[26]

  “Schizo­phrenia is not a dis­ease in one person but rather a crazy
362
way in which whole famil­ies func­tion. …”[27]

  “Schizo­phrenia, if it means any­thing, is a more or less char­ac­ter­istic mode of dis­turbed group beha­viour. There are no schizo­phrenics.[28]


s6
THE FAMILY—“FROM GOOD TO BAD TO MAD”


  “Over the last two dec­ades there has been a grow­ing dis­satis­fac­tion with any theory or study of the indi­vidual which ar­ti­fi­cially isol­ates him from the con­text of his life, inter­per­sonal and so­cial.”


  Sartre holds that all groups are struc­tured against an aware­ness of a “spec­tator”. This “spec­tator” may be an indi­vidual—as in the case of chil­dren seeing them­selves as “pupils” in rela­tion to a teacher—or an­other group, as in the case of workers con­sti­tu­ting them­selves against man­agers. This spac­tator he calls the “Third” for whom the group ex­ists as an object. Laing and Cooper seem to have de­veloped their views on groups{{dash|and in par­tic­u­lar, the family system of the future “schizo­phrenic”from Sartre’s inter­preta­tion of group struc­ture and cohe­sion. In elab­or­at­ing their theories the British ex­isten­tial ana­lysts have made use of a number of terms, some of their own crea­tion, whilst others are also used by Sartre. This rather tech­nical and eso­teric lan­guage creates a dens­ity in some of their writing which ob­scures the im­port­ance of what is being said; in my view, the value of Laing and Cooper’s book Reason and Viol­ence is much re­duced by their over-​reli­ance on such terms and it is a pity that what one senses to be im­port­ant ideas are couched in lan­guage which re­quires a good deal of de­cipher­ing before it becomes in­tel­ligible. If this par­tic­u­lar book had been in ex­ist­ence at the time Orwell was pre­paring his essay “Polit­ics and the English Lan­guage” it would have pro­vided him with some re­mark­able cau­tion­ary ex­tracts.

  The British ex­ist­en­tial­ists make use of two words, series and nexus, in dif­fer­en­ti­ating between kinds of group—and two words, praxis and pro­cess, which de­scribe group dy­nam­ics or the rela­tion­ships between group mem­bers. A series is typic­ally, a human as­so­ci­a­tion on negat­ive grounds—for ex­ample a bus queue in which the sole link between per­sons is a com­mon desire to travel on the bus; each person in the queue being “one too many” for the others. Also re­garded as series are per­sons united solely on the basis of op­posi­tion to some shared con­cept: anti-​semites sharing only their hatred of Jews, or one could per­haps say anarch­ists, united by shared op­posi­tion to the state (the only belief com­mon to all anarch­ist views). A series may move towards being a group through “an act of group-​syn­thesis” (Laing’s term). “If I think of cer­tain others as together with me, and cer­tain others as not together with me, I have already under­taken two acts of syn­thesis, re­sult­ing in we and them. However, in order that we have a group iden­tity, it is not enough that I re­gard, let us say, you and him as con­sti­tu­ting a we with myself. You and he have to per­form sim­ilar acts of syn­thesis, each on his own behalf. In this we (me, and you, and him), each of us recog­nises not only our own private syn­theses, but also the syn­theses that each of the others makes.”[29]

  The dis­tinct­ive qual­ities of the nexus are that each person ac­know­
363
ledges: the need of each for the others; the ex­ist­ence of strong bonds between mem­bers (not main­tained prin­cip­ally by in­sti­tu­tional or organ­isa­tion struc­tures, or a shared ex­ternal “com­mon ob­ject”. “The rela­tion­ships of per­sons in a nexus are char­ac­ter­ised by en­dur­ing and in­tens­ive face-​to-​face recip­rocal in­flu­ence on each other’s ex­peri­ence and beha­viour.”[30] The family, or at least the family as we are ac­cus­tomed to think of it, is repre­sent­at­ive of a nexus.

  Praxis and pro­cess are both terms used by Sartre. Basic­ally, praxis is what is done by some­one: “deeds done by doers”, “the acts of an indi­vidual or group”; whilst pro­cess re­fers to “what just hap­pens”, activ­ity not in­tended by any­one and of which no one person in a group may be aware.

  The posi­tion of the person within the group will af­fect his idea of him­self—of who he is. In the same way his view of others in the group af­fects their defin­i­tions of them­selves. And again, his beha­viour will be af­fected by his idea of what other people make of him. As a person moves during even one day, from group to group, from one mode of as­so­ci­a­tion to an­other, he must adapt him­self to each con­text: “Each group re­quires more or less rad­ical in­ternal trans­forma­tion of the per­sons who com­prise it. Con­sider the meta­morph­oses that the one man may go through in one day … family man, speck of crowd dust, func­tion­ary in the organ­isa­tion, friend. These are not simply dif­fer­ent roles: each is a whole past and present and future, of­fer­ing dif­fer­ing op­tions and con­straints, dif­fer­ent degrees of change or iner­tia, dif­fer­ent kinds of close­ness and dis­tance, dif­fer­ent sets of rights and ob­liga­tions, dif­fer­ent pledges and pro­mises.”[31]

  Dr. Laing’s second book The Self and Others deals with the way in which a person is af­fected by his situ­ation in a “nexus” of others, in par­tic­u­lar within the family. “The others either can con­trib­ute to the per­son’s self-​ful­fil­ment, or they can be a potent factor in his losing him­self (ali­en­a­tion) even to the point of mad­ness.” He as­serts his belief that “fantasy is a mode of ex­peri­ence” and that rela­tion­ships on a fantasy level are “as basic to all human rela­ted­ness as the inter­ac­tions that most people most of the time are more aware of.”

  What hap­pens in the fam­il­ies of “schizo­phrenics”? It is im­port­ant to em­phas­ise that it is not the thesis of these workers that the family rather than the indi­vidual is “ill”. A group is not an organ­ism—even though it may ap­pear to be one to its mem­bers or to ob­servers out­side it. A human group of what­ever size, does not pos­sess either a body or a mind that can be either well or ill. In the family, a per­son’s self can be either con­firmed or dis­con­firmed by the actions and in­flu­ence—in­clud­ing in­flu­ence in “fantasy”—of others in the family nexus. Mysti­fi­ca­tion of a person can be car­ried so far that all genu­ine ex­pres­sions of in­depend­ent de­velop­ment are denied valid­ity. “in the fam­il­ies of schizo­phrenic pa­tients in­ten­tions, which link up with the ‘psy­chotic acts’ of the pa­tient are denied, or even, their anti­thesis as­serted so that the pa­tient’s actions have the ap­pear­ance of pure pro­cess un­related to praxis and may even be ex­peri­enced by him as such.”[32] In the moving final sec­tion of The Divided Self (called “The Ghost of the Weed
364
Garden”) R. D. Laing de­scribes the clin­ical bio­graphy of a schizo­phrenic. This was based on a series of inter­views with the pa­tient, mem­bers of the pa­tient’s family, both indi­vidu­ally and jointly with other mem­bers. These inter­views were de­signed to secure the in­forma­tion neces­sary for an ex­ist­en­tial ana­lysis and were not a form of group psy­cho­ther­apy. It is here that Laing first out­lines the se­quence which would ap­pear to be typical of this kind of family inter­ac­tion: whilst each family mem­ber had his or her own view of the pa­tient-​to-​be’s life, they all agreed on three basic phases:
  1. “The pa­tient was a good, normal, healthy child; until she gradu­ally began
  2. “to be bad, to do or say things that caused great dis­tress, and which were on the whole ‘put down’ to naughti­ness or bad­ness, until
  3. “this went beyond all toler­able limits so that she could only be re­garded as com­pletely mad.”

What was seen by the mother as her daugh­ter’s “good” period, in infancy and early child­hood, she de­scribed with such re­marks as “she gave no trouble”, “she always did what she was told”. Laing com­ments that what to the mother were signs of good­ness, were signs that the child had never been per­mit­ted to become “ex­ist­en­tially alive”—in fact “being ex­ist­en­tially dead re­ceives the high­est com­menda­tion”. The “bad” period was the time of ad­oles­cence, during which the pa­tient made her great­est strug­gle towards a real­isa­tion of her own self through auto­nom­ous action but found that her ef­forts were con­tinu­ally de­feated by “the com­plete ab­sence of any­one in her world who could or would see some sense in her point of view”. The trans­fer from “bad” to “mad” came as some­thing of a relief to the rest of the family, who “blamed them­selves for not real­ising sooner”. As the mother said: “I knew she really could not have meant the awful things she said to me. In a way, I blame myself but, in a way, I’m glad that it was an ill­ness after all, but if only I had not waited so long before I took her to a doctor.”

  In San­ity, Mad­ness and the Family (the first volume of an un­com­pleted study) Drs. Laing and Esterson present ex­tracts from inter­views with mem­bers of 11 fam­il­ies, all of which con­tained daugh­ters dia­gnosed as “schizo­phrenic”. In the Intro­duc­tion to this book the authors write “… we believe that we show that the ex­peri­ence and beha­viour of schizo­phrenics is much more so­cially intel­li­gible than has come to be sup­posed by most psy­chi­atrists … we believe that the shift of point of view that these de­scrip­tions both em­body and de­mand has an histor­ical sig­ni­fic­ance no less rad­ical than the shift from a demon­o­log­ical to a clin­ical view­point 300 years ago.” Beha­viour which is eventu­ally inter­preted by the family as a sign of mad­ness is, they argue, the out­ward ex­pres­sion of a desper­ate at­tempt on the part of the “mad one” to “make sense of a sense­less situ­ation”—to pre­serve some au­then­tic ele­ments of per­son­ality—a strug­gle for auto­nomy, spon­tan­eity, re­spons­ibil­ity and “free­dom”. Here is an ex­cerpt from Laing and Esterson’s tran­script of Mr. and Mrs. Gold’s ac­count of their daughter: “When she is her ‘real’ self, that is, when she is ‘well’, she is not to be seri­ously inter­ested in writers or art, not to wear col­oured stock­ings, not to listen to jazz in a jazz club, not to bring friends home, not to stay out late. It is only from time to time that Ruth tries to as­sert her­self over against this par­ental eternal es­sence, and when she does she wears clothes to her liking, and in­sists vehem­ently on going where and with whom she wishes. Then her mother ‘knows’ and ‘at­tack’ is coming on. She is told she is being dif­fi­cult, in­con­sider­ate, dis­re­spect­ful, thought­less, because she is causing her parents such anxi­ety—but they do not blame or hold her re­spons­ible for all this, because they know she is odd and ill. Thus mys­ti­fied and put in an in­toler­able posi­tion she becomes ex­cited and desper­ate, makes ‘wild’ ac­cus­a­tions that her parents do not want her to live, and runs out of the house. …”[33]

  These writers claim, and I think demon­strate, that armed with a know­ledge of the pa­tient’s ex­ist­en­tial situ­ation, it is pos­sible to make sense of what “psy­chi­atrists still by and large re­gard as non­sense”. For example, Julie, the pa­tient in “The Ghost of the Weed Garden” re­ferred to her­self whilst in her “psy­chotic” state as “Mrs. Taylor” and as a “tolled bell”. Dr. Laing inter­prets her chosen title “Mrs. Taylor” as ex­pres­sing the feel­ings: “I’m tailor made; I’m a tailored maid; I was made, fed, clothed and tailored” and a “tolled bell” is also “the told belle” “the girl who always did what she was told”. The schizo­phrenic’s “delu­sions” of per­secu­tion are real ex­pres­sions of re­ac­tion in re­sponse to real per­secu­tion and are ex­ist­en­tially true; that is to say they are “liter­ally true state­ments within the terms of refer­ence of the indi­vidual who makes them.”††

  The person is now launched on a “career” as a mental pa­tient. He is con­firmed in this role by so­ciety’s agents the psy­chi­atrists, in col­lu­sion with the pa­tient’s family, and by pro­cess of be­trayal and de­grada­tion[34] becomes an in­mate of a mental hos­pital, which in­sti­tu­tion em­bodies “a so­cial struc­ture which in many re­spects re­du­plic­ates the mad­den­ing pecu­li­ar­ities of the pa­tient’s family … he finds psy­chi­atrists, ad­min­is­trat­ors, nurses who are his verit­able par­ents, broth­ers, sisters, who play an inter­per­sonal game which only too often re­sembles in the in­tric­a­cies of its rules the game he failed in at home.”[35]

  The ex­ist­en­tial ana­lysts have as­serted that a great deal of what passes for treat­ment in mental in­sti­tu­tions is viol­ence. Per­haps we can now begin to see what is meant by this. David Cooper in his art­icle in Views, No. 8 quotes Sartre’s defin­i­tion of viol­ence: “The cor­ros­ive
366
action of the free­dom of a person on the free­dom of an­other.” And he ex­plains this: “The action of a person … can de­stroy the free­dom of an­other or at least para­lyse it by mys­ti­fica­tion.” In an art­icle printed in Peace News (22.1.65) called “Mas­sacre of the In­no­cents” R. D. Laing makes his under­stand­ing of the word clear: “Love and viol­ence, pro­perly speak­ing, are polar op­pos­ites. Love lets the other be, but with af­fec­tion and con­cern. Viol­ence at­tempts to con­strain the other’s free­dom, to force him to act in the way we desire, but with ultim­ate lack of con­cern, with in­dif­fer­ence to the other’s own ex­ist­ence or des­tiny.” The basic theme of his art­icle is that a most brutal and de­struct­ive form of viol­ence is “viol­ence mas­quer­ad­ing as love”. In rela­tion to the family and its “schizo­phrenic” mem­ber, action to secure care and at­ten­tion in hos­pital for some­one who is “ill” could well be inter­preted as an ex­pres­sion of con­cern and love. Whether or not one believes that this pro­cess and the pa­tient’s sub­sequent treat­ment is a form of viol­ence will de­pend in part, on whether one believes that there is any ill­ness “in” the person to be “cured”. It is not viol­ence to am­pu­tate a gan­gren­ous leg. We would all agree that it would be a viol­ent pro­ject to per­suade a person that his leg was dis­eased (“because you do not keep in step with us …”), to find a sur­geon who believes that there is a so­cial need for one-​legged people—and for him to cut off the leg. In the actual case of the hos­pital­ised schizo­phrenic each person in the chain sees himself as acting in the best inter­ests of the others … “but we have also to re­mem­ber that good in­ten­tions and all the wrap­pings of re­spect­abil­ity very often cover a truly cruel human real­ity.”[36]


THEORIES IN PRACTICE: “THE ANTI-HOSPITAL”



* See The Divided Self, pp. 41-42. For an ac­count of the con­sequences of the ob­struc­tion of this oc­cur­rence: “an ex­ist­en­tially dead child” see p. 183. In Views, No. 8, David Cooper writes: “… the begin­ning of per­sonal de­velop­ment is never pure passiv­ity. … From the first moment of mother-child inter­action, where each is an­other to the other, the child is in the posi­tion of having to ini­ti­ate the pro­ject to become who­ever he is to be, and this is in prin­ciple a free choice, his free crea­tion of his essen­tial nature.”

** An art­icle in The Observer (4.9.66) an­nounced the forma­tion of “Pro­ject 70”—“a plan to rescue men­tally normal old people from the wards of mental hos­pitals.”

*** This may be an al­lu­sion to a case which was re­ceiv­ing some pub­li­city at that time. Zenya Belov, a student, was con­fined in a Russian mental in­sti­tu­tion around Septem­ber, 1965—and he is pre­sum­ably still there. It was al­leged that he had shown “schizo­phrenic symp­toms” (“drawing dia­grams, trying to re­organ­ise the world graph­ic­ally”) but the only “symp­toms” evid­ent to the British students who were with him shortly before the onset of “ill­ness” were his “un­ortho­dox and re­form­ist polit­ical views”.

Refer­ences to a letter from Brenda Jordan in Peace News (17.6.66).

†† See also Laing’s inter­preta­tion of the state­ments of a schizo­phrenic from the ori­ginal ac­count in Kraepelin’s Lec­tures on Clin­ical Psy­chi­atry, 1905 (pp. 29-31 The Divided Self). Laing writes: “What does this pa­tient seem to be doing? Surely he is carry­ing on a dia­logue between his own par­od­ied ver­sion of Kraepelin, and his own defi­ant rebel­ling self. ‘You want to know that too? I tell you who is being meas­ured and is meas­ured and shall be meas­ured. I know all that, and I could tell you, but I do not want to’.” Laing com­ments: “This seems to be plain enough talk.”


Relev­ant Books and Art­icles not men­tioned in Refer­ences:


R. D. Laing, “Series and Nexus in the Family”, New Left Review, No. 15.

David Cooper, “Sartre on Genet”, New Left Review, No. 25.

R. D. Laing, The Polit­ics of Ex­peri­ence and the Bird of Para­dise, Penguin Books, Autumn, 1966.

R. D. Laing, H. Phillip­son, A. R. Lee, Inter­per­sonal Per­cep­tion: A Theory and a Method, London, Tavistock, 1966.

T. S. Szasz, The Myth of Mental Ill­ness, London, Seeker and Warburg, 1962.

Carl R. Rogers, On Becoming a Person, London, Constable & Co., 1961.


NOTES


<references>

  1. Robert G. Olson, An Intro­duc­tion to Ex­ist­en­tial­ism, New York, Dover Publi­ca­tions, 1962, p. 52.
  2. ibid., p. 105 (a refer­ence to an epis­ode in Being and No­thing­ness, p. 495).
  3. J.-P. Sartre, Situations III, Paris, Gallimard, 1949 (quoted by Olson, p. 121).
  4. Olson, op. cit., p. 119.
  5. Sartre J.-P. Sartre, Being and No­thing­ness, London, Methuen, 1956, pp. 461-2.
  6. ibid., pp. 471-75 (quoted by Olson, p. 121).
  7. The first part of R. D. Laing’s The Self and Others is a lucid argu­ment against the basic con­cepts of tradi­tional psycho-ana­lysis.
  8. “Mas­sacre of the In­no­cents”, Peace News, 22nd January, 1965.
  9. BBCPanorama” on “Mental Health”, 6th June, 1966.
  10. David Cooper, “The Anti-​Hos­pital: An Ex­peri­ment in Psy­chi­atry”, New So­ciety, 11th March, 1965.
  11. David Cooper, “Viol­ence in Psy­chi­atry”, Views, No. 8, Summer, 1965.
  12. ibid.
  13. Part of a letter by Pierre-​Joseph Brie, “In­san­ity and the Egg”, Peace News, 1st July, 1966.
  14. T. S. Szasz, “Polit­ics and Mental Health”, Amer­ican Journal of Psy­chi­atry, No. 115 (1958) (quoted by Erving Goffman in Asylums, p. 509).
  15. Erving Goffman, <span data-html="true" class="plainlinks" title="Wikipedia: Asylums—Essays on the So­cial Situ­a­tion of Mental Pa­tients and Other In­mates">Asylums—Essays on the So­cial Situ­a­tion of Mental Pa­tients and Other In­mates, New York, Anchor Books, 1961, pp. 363-4.
  16. ibid., p. 354.
  17. ibid., p. 135.
  18. ibid., p. 380.
  19. For a re­con­struc­tion of a psy­chi­atric inter­roga­tion see “The Case Con­fer­ence”, Views, No. 11, Summer, 1966. <span data-html="true" class="plainlinks" title="Wikipedia: Elias Canetti<!-­- 'Elia Canetti' in original -->">Elias Canetti<!-­- 'Elia Canetti' in original --> has written that “ques­tion­ing is a for­cible in­tru­sion. When used as an in­stru­ment of power, it is like a knife cut­ting into the flesh of the vic­tim. … The most blat­ant tyranny is the one that asks the most ques­tions” (Crowds and Power, Gollancz, 1962).
  20. A sen­tence of Dr. Joshua Dierer’s, speak­ing at the World Federa­tion of Mental Health, 1960 (quoted by Colin Ward in “Where The Shoe Pinches”, anarchy 4).
  21. Goffman, op. cit., p. 384.
  22. An estim­ate made by the Swiss psy­chi­atrist E. Bleuler, quoted by David Cooper in “The Anti-​Hos­pital”.
  23. P. Rube, “Heal­ing Pro­cess in Schizo­phrenia”, Journal of Nervous and Mental Dis­eases, 1948 (quoted by John Linsie in “Schizo­phrenia: A So­cial Dis­ease”, anarchy 24).
  24. R. D. Laing, “What is Schizo­phrenia?”, New Left Review, No. 28.
  25. R. D. Laing and A. Esterson, San­ity, Mad­ness and the Family, London, Tavi­stock, 1964.
  26. R. D. Laing, “What is Schizo­phrenia?”, op. cit.
  27. David Cooper, “The Anti-Hos­pital”, op. cit.
  28. David Cooper, Viol­ence in Psy­chi­atry, Views, No. 8.
  29. R. D. Laing, “Us and Them”, Views, No. 11.
  30. R. D. Laing and A. Esterson, op. cit.
  31. R. D. Laing, “Us and Them”, op. cit.
  32. David Cooper, “Two Types of Ration­ality”, New Left Review, No. 29.
  33. op. cit., p. 155.
  34. Erving Goffman in Asylums makes use of the term “career” to de­note “the so­cial strand” of a per­son’s life in­au­gur­ated at the moment of his defin­i­tion as a mental pa­tient; “be­trayal fun­nel” to de­scribe the cir­cuit of figures (relat­ives, psy­chi­atrists, etc.) whose inter­ac­tions end with the pa­tient’s con­fine­ment in the
    374
    asylum, and “de­grada­tion ce­re­mo­nial” for the psy­chi­atric exam­ina­tion pre­ced­ing the pa­tient’s ad­mis­sion.
  35. David Cooper, “Viol­ence in Psy­chi­atry”, op. cit.
  36. ibid.