Difference between revisions of "Anarchy 70/Libertarian Psychiatry: an introduction to existential analysis"
imported>Ivanhoe |
imported>Ivanhoe |
||
Line 29: | Line 29: | ||
{{tab}}{{qq|Man can­not be some­times slave and some­times free; he is wholly and forever free, or he is not free at all.}} | {{tab}}{{qq|Man can­not be some­times slave and some­times free; he is wholly and forever free, or he is not free at all.}} | ||
− | <div style="text-align:right;">Sartre: ''{{w|Being and No­thing­ness|Being_and_Nothingness}}''</div> | + | <div style="text-align:right;">{{w|Sartre|Jean-Paul_Sartre}}: ''{{w|Being and No­thing­ness|Being_and_Nothingness}}''</div> |
− | {{tab}}The con­cept of free­dom at the core of ex­ist­en­tial­ism is very dif­fer­ent from what I take to be the com­mon under­stand­ing of the term. In gen­eral usage, a man is free in as much as he can achieve his chosen ends with a min­imum of effort. Simil­arly, a man{{s}} free­dom is re­duced as the ob­stacles between his de­sires and chosen ends are in­creased. Free­dom is re­garded as a measur­able quant­ity; one may have a lot or a little of it, and it can be taken away{{dash}}or even {{qq|given}}. The anarch­ist{{s}} hypo­thet­ical destin­a­tion, the {{qq|free}} so­ciety, may often be thought of in the sense of an har­mo­ni­ous envir­on­ment in which all re­mov­able ob­stacles between man{{s}} de­sires and their ful­fil­ment have been elim­in­ated. But for Sartre, man is totally free by reason of his very being as man, and ob­stacles between de­sires and chosen ends are of no rel­ev­ance. To use a favoured ex­ist­en­tial­ist phrase, man is free by onto­lo­gical neces­sity. But his free­dom rests, within this con­cept, in his total re­spons­ibil­ity in the face of un­deter­mined choice and in his recog­ni­tion of the in­escap­able ob­lig­a­tion to choose. An intuit­ive aware­ness of this re­spons­ib­il­ity{{dash|per­haps pro­voked by some sort of {{qq|ex­treme situ­a­tion}}}}gives rise to what Sartre calls {{qq|the anguish of free­dom}}. It is our fate to be free. {{qq|… One must always de­cide for one­self and efforts to shift the burden of re­spons­ib­il­ity upon others are neces­sar­ily self-<wbr>de­feat­ing. Not to choose is also to choose, for even if we de­liver our power of de­ci­sion to others, we are still re­spons­ible for having done so. It is always the indi­vidual who de­cides that others will choose for him.}}<ref>Robert G. Olson, ''An Intro­duc­tion to Ex­ist­en­tial­ism'', New York, Dover Publi­ca­tions, 1962, p. 52.</ref> In so far as we are free in our choices, we {{qq|create}} the ob­stacles that lie between our pro­ject and its ful­fil­ment: {{qq|an in­sig­ni­fic­ant public of­fi­cial in {{w|Mont-de-Marsan|Mont-de-Marsan}} without means may not have the op­por­tun­ity to go to {{w|New York|New_York}} if that be his ambi­tion. But the ob­stacles which stand in his way would not exist as ob­stacles were it not for his free choice and values: in this case, his desire to go {{p|355}}to New York.}}<ref>ibid., p. 105 (a refer­ence to an epis­ode in ''Being and No­thing­ness'', p. 495).</ref> Even though human free­dom, in his view, is total, Sartre ad­mits of a sense in which it may be spoken of in terms of degree. A man may be said to become {{qq|more free}} as his con­scious­ness of total free­dom and re­spons­ib­il­ity in­creases; and cer­tain situ­a­tions in life can crystal­lize this aware­ness. In an ap­par­ently cryptic para­graph in ''Being and No­thing­ness'' Sartre de­scribes the {{w|German Oc­cupa­tion of France|German_military_administration_in_occupied_France_during_World_War_II}} during the last {{w|war|World_War_II}} as such a situ­a­tion. {{qq|… the choice that each of us made of his life and his being was an au­then­tic choice because it was made face to face with death, because it could always have been ex­pressed in these terms: {{q|Rather death than …}}.}}<ref>{{w|J.-P. Sartre|Jean-Paul_Sartre}}, ''Situations III'', Paris, Gallimard, 1949 (quoted by {{popup|Olson|Robert G. Olson. An Introduction to Existentialism.}}, p. 121).</ref> But the issue is not just one of an in­creased sense of re­spons­ib­il­ity for our day-<wbr>to-<wbr>day options{{dash}}for in­stance in de­cid­ing upon a change in oc­cu­pa­tion, or merely which book to read next; most sig­ni­fic­antly ''we choose our­selves'', and our day-<wbr>to-<wbr>day de­ci­sions neces­sarily re­flect this primary choice we have made. We are what we have chosen to be. All our sub­sequent modes of action are re­lated to this original {{qq|project-<wbr>of-<wbr>being}}, {{qq|Freely chosen at the moment one wrenches one­self away from the in-<wbr>itself to create one{{s}} own world}}<ref>{{popup|Olson|Robert G. Olson}}, {{popup|op. cit.|opere citato: cited above}}, p. 119.</ref> (the in-<wbr>itself: the world of things). This event I take to be com­par­able with what R. D. Laing calls {{qq|ex­ist­en­tial birth}} which, he sug­gests, is as essen­tial for a fully human ex­ist­ence as the bio­lo­gical birth which it nor­mally follows.{{ref|aster|*}} It is only in rela­tion to this funda­mental choice, the indi­vidual{{s}} original {{qq|pro­ject-<wbr>of-<wbr>being}} that his later beha­viour can be fully under­stood. The plaus­ibil­ity of this basic idea is not in­creased by Sartre{{s}} denial of the divi­sion of the self into con­scious and un­con­scious modes; the idea of a tooth­less infant con­sciously de­termin­ing its future life­style and pur­pose is at first thought ab­surd. But whilst ex­pli­citly deny­ing valid­ity to the {{qq|un­con­scious}} Sartre does separ­ate con­scious­ness into {{qq|re­flect­ive}} and {{qq|non-<wbr>re­flect­ive}} levels, and it is at the non-<wbr>re­flect­ive level that this funda­mental choice is made. He stresses that this original choice is in no way de­liber­ate: {{qq|This is not because it would be less con­scious or less ex­plicit than a de­liber­a­tion but, on the con­trary, because it is the found­a­tion of all de­liber­a­tion and because … a de­liber­a­tion re­quires an inter­pret­a­tion in terms of an original choice.}}<ref>{{w|J.-P. Sartre|Jean- | + | {{tab}}The con­cept of free­dom at the core of ex­ist­en­tial­ism is very dif­fer­ent from what I take to be the com­mon under­stand­ing of the term. In gen­eral usage, a man is free in as much as he can achieve his chosen ends with a min­imum of effort. Simil­arly, a man{{s}} free­dom is re­duced as the ob­stacles between his de­sires and chosen ends are in­creased. Free­dom is re­garded as a measur­able quant­ity; one may have a lot or a little of it, and it can be taken away{{dash}}or even {{qq|given}}. The anarch­ist{{s}} hypo­thet­ical destin­a­tion, the {{qq|free}} so­ciety, may often be thought of in the sense of an har­mo­ni­ous envir­on­ment in which all re­mov­able ob­stacles between man{{s}} de­sires and their ful­fil­ment have been elim­in­ated. But for Sartre, man is totally free by reason of his very being as man, and ob­stacles between de­sires and chosen ends are of no rel­ev­ance. To use a favoured ex­ist­en­tial­ist phrase, man is free by onto­lo­gical neces­sity. But his free­dom rests, within this con­cept, in his total re­spons­ibil­ity in the face of un­deter­mined choice and in his recog­ni­tion of the in­escap­able ob­lig­a­tion to choose. An intuit­ive aware­ness of this re­spons­ib­il­ity{{dash|per­haps pro­voked by some sort of {{qq|ex­treme situ­a­tion}}}}gives rise to what Sartre calls {{qq|the anguish of free­dom}}. It is our fate to be free. {{qq|… One must always de­cide for one­self and efforts to shift the burden of re­spons­ib­il­ity upon others are neces­sar­ily self-<wbr>de­feat­ing. Not to choose is also to choose, for even if we de­liver our power of de­ci­sion to others, we are still re­spons­ible for having done so. It is always the indi­vidual who de­cides that others will choose for him.}}<ref>Robert G. Olson, ''An Intro­duc­tion to Ex­ist­en­tial­ism'', New York, Dover Publi­ca­tions, 1962, p. 52.</ref> In so far as we are free in our choices, we {{qq|create}} the ob­stacles that lie between our pro­ject and its ful­fil­ment: {{qq|an in­sig­ni­fic­ant public of­fi­cial in {{w|Mont-de-Marsan|Mont-de-Marsan}} without means may not have the op­por­tun­ity to go to {{w|New York|New_York}} if that be his ambi­tion. But the ob­stacles which stand in his way would not exist as ob­stacles were it not for his free choice and values: in this case, his desire to go {{p|355}}to New York.}}<ref>ibid., p. 105 (a refer­ence to an epis­ode in ''Being and No­thing­ness'', p. 495).</ref> Even though human free­dom, in his view, is total, Sartre ad­mits of a sense in which it may be spoken of in terms of degree. A man may be said to become {{qq|more free}} as his con­scious­ness of total free­dom and re­spons­ib­il­ity in­creases; and cer­tain situ­a­tions in life can crystal­lize this aware­ness. In an ap­par­ently cryptic para­graph in ''Being and No­thing­ness'' Sartre de­scribes the {{w|German Oc­cupa­tion of France|German_military_administration_in_occupied_France_during_World_War_II}} during the last {{w|war|World_War_II}} as such a situ­a­tion. {{qq|… the choice that each of us made of his life and his being was an au­then­tic choice because it was made face to face with death, because it could always have been ex­pressed in these terms: {{q|Rather death than …}}.}}<ref>{{w|J.-P. Sartre|Jean-Paul_Sartre}}, ''Situations III'', Paris, Gallimard, 1949 (quoted by {{popup|Olson|Robert G. Olson. An Introduction to Existentialism.}}, p. 121).</ref> But the issue is not just one of an in­creased sense of re­spons­ib­il­ity for our day-<wbr>to-<wbr>day options{{dash}}for in­stance in de­cid­ing upon a change in oc­cu­pa­tion, or merely which book to read next; most sig­ni­fic­antly ''we choose our­selves'', and our day-<wbr>to-<wbr>day de­ci­sions neces­sarily re­flect this primary choice we have made. We are what we have chosen to be. All our sub­sequent modes of action are re­lated to this original {{qq|project-<wbr>of-<wbr>being}}, {{qq|Freely chosen at the moment one wrenches one­self away from the in-<wbr>itself to create one{{s}} own world}}<ref>{{popup|Olson|Robert G. Olson}}, {{popup|op. cit.|opere citato: cited above}}, p. 119.</ref> (the in-<wbr>itself: the world of things). This event I take to be com­par­able with what R. D. Laing calls {{qq|ex­ist­en­tial birth}} which, he sug­gests, is as essen­tial for a fully human ex­ist­ence as the bio­lo­gical birth which it nor­mally follows.{{ref|aster|*}} It is only in rela­tion to this funda­mental choice, the indi­vidual{{s}} original {{qq|pro­ject-<wbr>of-<wbr>being}} that his later beha­viour can be fully under­stood. The plaus­ibil­ity of this basic idea is not in­creased by Sartre{{s}} denial of the divi­sion of the self into con­scious and un­con­scious modes; the idea of a tooth­less infant con­sciously de­termin­ing its future life­style and pur­pose is at first thought ab­surd. But whilst ex­pli­citly deny­ing valid­ity to the {{qq|un­con­scious}} Sartre does separ­ate con­scious­ness into {{qq|re­flect­ive}} and {{qq|non-<wbr>re­flect­ive}} levels, and it is at the non-<wbr>re­flect­ive level that this funda­mental choice is made. He stresses that this original choice is in no way de­liber­ate: {{qq|This is not because it would be less con­scious or less ex­plicit than a de­liber­a­tion but, on the con­trary, because it is the found­a­tion of all de­liber­a­tion and because … a de­liber­a­tion re­quires an inter­pret­a­tion in terms of an original choice.}}<ref>{{w|J.-P. Sartre|Jean-Paul_Sartre}}, {{w|''Being and No­thing­ness''|Being_and_Nothingness}}, London, Methuen, 1956, pp. 461-2.</ref> The con­cepts of {{qq|au­then­ti­city}} and its ap­proxim­ate op­po­site {{qq|bad-<wbr>faith}} are in a sense under­stand­able as judge­ments (al­though Sartre claims only to use these terms de­script­ively) upon the degree of con­cord­ance between the choices of our re­flect­ive con­scious­ness and our original pro­ject-<wbr>of-<wbr>being. In a pas­sage which bears di­rectly upon ex­ist­en­tial ana­lysis he writes that a man {{qq|can make vol­un­tary de­ci­sions which are op­posed to the funda­mental ends which he has chosen. These de­ci­sions can be only vol­un­tary{{dash}}that is, re­flect­ive. … Thus, for ex­ample, I can de­cide to cure myself of {{w|stutter­ing|Stuttering}}. I can even {{p|256}}suc­ceed in it. … In fact I can ob­tain a result by using merely tech­nical methods. … But these re­sults will only dis­place the in­firm­ity from which I suf­fer; an­other will arise in its place and will in its own way ex­press the total end which I pur­sue. … It is the same with these cures as it is with the cure of {{w|hys­teria|Hysteria}} by {{w|elec­tric shock treat­ment|Electroconvulsive_therapy}}. We know that this ther­apy can effect the dis­ap­pear­ance of an hys­terical con­trac­tion of the leg, but as one will see some time later the con­trac­tion will ap­pear in the arm. This is because the hys­teria can be cured only as a total­ity, for it is a total pro­ject of the for-<wbr>itself}}<ref>ibid., pp. 471-75 (quoted by {{popup|Olson|Robert G. Olson}}, p. 121).</ref> (the for-<wbr>itself: the world of con­scious­ness and in­ten­tion). |
{{tab}}Sartre argues against the {{w|Freud­ian|Sigmund_Freud}} three-<wbr>way split of the per­sonal­ity into {{w|id, ego and super-ego|Id,_ego_and_super-ego}} and the {{w|Psycho-ana­lytic|Psychoanalysis}} dictum of con­scious beha­viour as de­term­ined by drives, in­stincts and de­sires al­legedly eman­at­ing from the id. As Sartre{{s}} argu­ments hinge upon his stated belief in man{{s}} on­to­lo­gical free­dom, Freud{{s}} pro­ject of {{qq|de­term­ina­tion by the un­con­scious}} is met with similar ob­jec­tions to those made against other de­term­in­ist theories and I need not at­tempt to sum­mar­ise them here.<ref>The first part of {{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}}{{s}} ''The Self and Others'' is a lucid argu­ment against the basic con­cepts of tradi­tional psycho-<wbr>ana­lysis.</ref> The only valid form of ther­apy is one aimed at dis­cover­ing an indi­vidual{{s}} funda­mental pro­ject-<wbr>of-<wbr>being{{dash}}and this is the pur­pose of ex­ist­en­tial ana­lysis (or psycho-<wbr>ana­lysis; the pre­fix seems to be op­tional). {{qq|The prin­ciple of this psycho-<wbr>ana­lysis is that man is a total­ity and not a col­lec­tion; he there­fore ex­presses him­self in his total­ity in the most in­sig­ni­fic­ant and the most super­fi­cial as­pects of his con­duct}} (''Being and No­thing­ness''). Through the use of a tech­nique or method based on such as­sump­tions the ini­tially {{qq|crazy}} actions of the in­sane may be made com­pre­hens­ible{{dash}}and may even ap­pear {{qq|reason­able}} if a picture of the world in which the pa­tient lives can be as­sembled. | {{tab}}Sartre argues against the {{w|Freud­ian|Sigmund_Freud}} three-<wbr>way split of the per­sonal­ity into {{w|id, ego and super-ego|Id,_ego_and_super-ego}} and the {{w|Psycho-ana­lytic|Psychoanalysis}} dictum of con­scious beha­viour as de­term­ined by drives, in­stincts and de­sires al­legedly eman­at­ing from the id. As Sartre{{s}} argu­ments hinge upon his stated belief in man{{s}} on­to­lo­gical free­dom, Freud{{s}} pro­ject of {{qq|de­term­ina­tion by the un­con­scious}} is met with similar ob­jec­tions to those made against other de­term­in­ist theories and I need not at­tempt to sum­mar­ise them here.<ref>The first part of {{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}}{{s}} ''The Self and Others'' is a lucid argu­ment against the basic con­cepts of tradi­tional psycho-<wbr>ana­lysis.</ref> The only valid form of ther­apy is one aimed at dis­cover­ing an indi­vidual{{s}} funda­mental pro­ject-<wbr>of-<wbr>being{{dash}}and this is the pur­pose of ex­ist­en­tial ana­lysis (or psycho-<wbr>ana­lysis; the pre­fix seems to be op­tional). {{qq|The prin­ciple of this psycho-<wbr>ana­lysis is that man is a total­ity and not a col­lec­tion; he there­fore ex­presses him­self in his total­ity in the most in­sig­ni­fic­ant and the most super­fi­cial as­pects of his con­duct}} (''Being and No­thing­ness''). Through the use of a tech­nique or method based on such as­sump­tions the ini­tially {{qq|crazy}} actions of the in­sane may be made com­pre­hens­ible{{dash}}and may even ap­pear {{qq|reason­able}} if a picture of the world in which the pa­tient lives can be as­sembled. | ||
Line 131: | Line 131: | ||
− | '''THEORIES IN PRACTICE: {{qq|THE ANTI-HOSPITAL}} | + | '''THEORIES IN PRACTICE: {{qq|THE ANTI-HOSPITAL}}''' |
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | {{tab}}In his pamph­let ''Youth for Freedom'' (1951) [[Author:Tony Gibson|Tony Gibson]] wrote to the ef­fect that the chief value of {{w|Summer­hill|Summerhill_School}} to the com­mun­ity lay in its having taken the gen­eral con­cept of what a school should be and turned it on its head. Dr. David Cooper{{s}} {{popup|unit|Villa 21}} in {{w|a large mental hos­pital|Shenley_Hospital}} {{qq|just {{w|north{{-}}west of London|Shenley,_Hertfordshire}}}} has done very much the same thing to the gen­eral con­cept of the asylum. To main­tain the edu­ca­tional par­al­lel, Dr. Cooper{{s}} ex­peri­ment (judging from his ac­count of it in ''{{w|New So­ciety|New_Society}}''<ref>''{{w|New So­ciety|New_Society}}'', 11th March, 1965.</ref> also has great rel­ev­ance for those who would wish to at­tack the viol­ence im­plicit in the cus­tom­ary methods of so­cial organ­isa­tion in schools. | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{tab}}The theor­et­ical basis of the ex­peri­ment rested on the find­ings of Laing and Esterson, pub­lished in ''San­ity, Mad­ness and the Family''. I hope already to have given some idea of what these find­ings were: the family pre­serves its in­au­thentic system by using one of its mem­bers as a kind of {{qq|scape­goat}}, ending by at­trib­ut­ing mad­ness to him. In gen­eral, so­ciety con­firms the at­trib­u­tions made by the {{qq|sane}} relat­ives and in­valid­ates the pa­tient{{s}} ver­sion of events by trans­lat­ing them into {{qq|symp­toms of a dis­ease}}. The bear­ing of this theory on the psy­chi­atric ward, writes Dr. Cooper, is that {{qq|staff must begin to refuse to enter into the tradi­tional covert col­lu­sion with the pa­tient{{s}} family. In the past this col­lu­sion has often meant that staff become im­plic­ated in a pro­gres­sive viol­ence that is per­petu­ated, in the name of treat­ment, {{p|367}}against the la­belled pa­tient.}} The workers on the {{qq|anti{{-}}hos­pital}} pro­ject main­tained one central con­vic­tion: that it was neces­sary to under­stand, in some meas­ure, the pro­cesses going on in them­selves before they could hope to have real in­sight into the {{qq|inner}} world of their pa­tients. | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{tab}}The unit{{dash|one ward in a hos­pital of some 2,300 pa­tients}}opened in January, 1962, with 19 young male pa­tients, two{{-}}thirds of whom had been dia­gnosed as {{qq|having}} schizo­phrenia. They had all been previ­ously in the insulin{{-}}coma ward. In the second year, the number of pa­tients was in­creased to 30. | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{tab}}The pro­gramme during the first year was highly struc­tured, with daily meet­ings of the whole staff{{-}}pa­tient group, separ­ate and regular staff meet­ings, {{w|oc­cu­pa­tional ther­apy|Occupational_therapy}} and organ­ised re­cre­ational activ­ity. No {{qq|phys­ical}} treat­ments were used except for the occa­sional dose of mild {{w|tran­quil­liser|Tranquilizer}}, and there was no indi­vidual {{w|psycho{{-}}ther­apy|Psychotherapy}}; there were however regu­lar {{qq|inter­views}} between ther­ap­ist and pa­tient and ther­ap­ist and pa­tient<!-- possibly a typo --> with vari­ous mem­bers of his family. After about a year, the staff became dis­satis­fied with the rigid­ities of the system and changes in the direc­tion of greater flu­id­ity were felt to be ap­pro­priate. | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{tab}}Dr. Cooper writes of two areas in which the con­sequent {{qq|de­struc­tur­ing}} had re­mark­able ef­fects{{dash}}the tradi­tional busi­ness of get­ting pa­tients out of bed in the morn­ing and the at­ti­tude to the pro­vi­sion of work and activ­ities. {{qq|One of the com­mon­est staff fan­tasies in mental hos­pitals is that if pa­tients are not co­erced verbally or phys­ic­ally into get­ting out of bed at a cer­tain hour in the morn­ing they will stay in bed until they rot away.}} This fantasy, like all anxi­ety over punc­tu­ality, is a form of pro­jec­tion. For the staff, the pa­tient re­pre­sents {{qq|that fright­en­ing as­pect of them­selves that some­times does not want to get out of bed in the morn­ing and come to work.}} After con­sider­able dis­cus­sion and the trial of vari­ous ap­proaches by dif­fer­ent staff groups it was found that if the usual {{qq|rous­ing pro­ced­ures}} were aban­doned the pa­tient did get up him­self{{dash}}even if he {{qq|re­belled}} to the ex­tent of re­main­ing in bed most of the day for a week or more. {{qq|No one rotted away after all and the gain in per­sonal auto­nomy seemed worth while.}} Dr. Cooper re­lates one epi­sode when {{qq|all the oc­cu­pants of a six{{-}}bed dorm­it­ory re­belled against the com­mun­ity meet­ing by stay­ing in bed until after 11 o’clock. One of the charge nurses went up­stairs to see what was going on. One of the pa­tients left to go to the toilet and the nurse seized the oppor­tun­ity to take off his white coat (worn not as uni­form but as pro­tect­ive clothing for cer­tain messy jobs like washing up) and climb into the vacant bed. The pa­tient, on his return, ap­pre­ci­at­ing the irony of the situ­ation, had little option but to take the va­cated {{q|staff role}}, put on the white coat and get the others out of bed.}} | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{tab}}The motiv­at­ing fantasy or belief behind the pro­vi­sion of work and {{qq|oc­cu­pa­tional ther­apy}} activ­ities is fre­quently that this in some way pro­tects the pa­tients from the erod­ing ef­fects of in­sti­tu­tion­al­isa­tion. But Dr. Cooper ob­serves: {{qq|The bitter truth is that if they sub­mis­sively {{p|368}}carry out all these re­quired tasks they become what is im­plied by these labels anyhow.}} If one wishes to en­counter the ul­ti­mate in with­drawn chronic in­sti­tu­tion­al­isa­tion one has only to visit one of the more {{qq|active}} and pro­duct­ive {{qq|factor­ies in a hos­pital}} or {{qq|indus­trial oc­cu­pa­tional ther­apy de­part­ments}}. In the unit, dis­cus­sion centred on this theme; the pa­tients were in any case show­ing re­sist­ance to con­ven­tional pro­jects. Jobs of a vigor­ous, de­struct­ive kind ({{qq|knock­ing down an {{w|air{{-}}raid shelter|Air_raid_shelter}}}}) which within a cer­tain mytho­logy, would have been sup­posed to pro­vide a proper out­let for ag­gres­sion, were not tackled with en­thu­si­asm. {{qq|People had real reasons to be angry with real other people at home and in hos­pital.}} Ham­mer­ing away at brick walls was of no rel­ev­ance. Partly as a result of fail­ure to hold the pa­tient{{s}} inter­est in tasks such as these{{dash|des­pite an at­tempt to in­flu­ence them by reduc­tion of their money al­low­ance}}a situ­ation was reached in which {{qq|no organ­ised work pro­ject was pre­sented to the com­mun­ity}}. The oc­cu­pa­tional ther­ap­ist de­cided that she would be better em­ployed in the unit as an assist­ant nurse. It was at this stage of de­velop­ments that the staff became con­scious of the break­down of role bound­ar­ies: {{qq|There was a pro­gres­sive blur­ring of role between nurses, doctor, oc­cu­pa­tional ther­ap­ist and pa­tients which brought into focus a number of dis­turb­ing and ap­par­ently para­dox­ical ques­tions: for ex­ample, can pa­tients {{q|treat}} other pa­tients and can they even treat staff? Can staff real­ise quite frankly and ac­know­ledge in the com­mun­ity their own areas of in­ca­pa­city and {{q|ill­ness}} and their need for {{q|treat­ment}}? If they did what would happen next and who would con­trol it?|r}} | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{tab}}{{qq|It was at this point that the most rad­ical de­par­ture from con­ven­tional psy­chi­atric work was ini­ti­ated. If the staff re­jected pre­scribed ideas about their func­tion and if they did not quite know what to do next, why do any­thing? Why not with­draw from the whole field of hos­pital staff and pa­tient ex­pect­ation in terms of organ­ising pa­tients into activ­ity, super­vis­ing the ward do­mestic work and gen­erally {{q|treat­ing pa­tients}}.}} After this, the staff re­tained con­trol of the issu­ing of drugs and con­tinued their ad­min­is­trat­ive work. Other sec­tions of the hos­pital were made aware of the policy change in the unit and the de­tails of the new ap­proach were clari­fied at the com­mun­ity meet­ings. The im­me­di­ate ef­fect of the change was re­flected in piles of washing{{-}}up left un­done and a marked in­crease in dirt. The normal level of staff anxi­ety in­creased as the pa­tients gave no sign of organ­ising among them­selves. The pa­tients were di­vided between those who wanted a re­turn to the pre­vi­ous system and others who {{qq|ap­pre­ci­ated the more au­thentic ele­ments in the policy change}}. The crisis point came during Dr. Cooper{{s}} ab­sence on holi­day. Up to that time, many of the staff had found as­sur­ance in the belief that the evid­ent dis­order was a con­sequence of en­act­ing the Doctor{{s}} {{qq|ultra{{-}}per­mis­sive policy{{dash}}they had done his bid­ding and what hap­pened was ul­ti­mately his re­spons­ib­il­ity. But during the period of his ab­sence, they acted together to put a limit to their in­tense anxi­ety and re­intro­duced some con­trols within the ward. This, Dr. Cooper sug­gests, was an ad­vance on their part in that they achieved a joint deci­sion and all mem­bers of the unit began to {{p|369}}ex­peri­ence the real de­mands made by the {{qq|group real­ity}}. Dr. Cooper{{s}} ob­serva­tions at this point are inter­est­ing and re­call the dis­tinc­tions made by other writers between forms of au­thor­ity{{dash}}{{qq|func­tional or ar­bit­rary}} ([[Author:Martin Buber|Martin Buber]]) {{qq|overt or an­onym­ous}} ({{w|Erich Fromm|Erich_Fromm}}). Dr. Cooper writes: {{qq|This leads us on to the central prob­lem of the psy­chi­atric hos­pital of dis­tin­guish­ing between au­thentic and in­au­thentic au­thor­ity. … The au­thor­ity of the au­thor­ity person is granted him by ar­bit­rary so­cial defin­ition rather than on the basis of any real ex­pert­ise he may pos­sess. If staff have the cour­age to shift them­selves from this false posi­tion they may dis­cover real sources of au­thor­ity in them­selves. They may also dis­cover such sources of au­thor­ity in {{q|the others}} who are de­fined as their pa­tients. … Per­haps the most central char­ac­ter­istic of au­thentic leader­ship is the re­lin­quish­ing of the im­pulse to domin­ate others. Domin­ation here means con­trol­ling the beha­viour of others where their beha­viour repre­sents for the leader pro­jected as­pects of his own ex­peri­ence. By domin­ation of the other the leader pro­duces for him­self the illu­sion that his own in­ternal organ­isa­tion is more and more per­fectly ordered. The {{w|Nazi|Nazi_Germany}} {{w|ex­term­in­ation camps|Extermination_camp}} were one pro­duct of this Dream of Per­fec­tion. The mental hos­pital, along with other in­sti­tu­tions in our so­ciety, is an­other.}} Sub­sti­tute {{qq|school}} for {{qq|psy­chi­atric hos­pital}} and {{qq|pupil}} for {{qq|pa­tient}} and one sees the wider rel­ev­ance of this pas­sage. | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{tab}}The work­ers in the unit were faced with con­flict­ing pres­sures{{dash|pres­sures to con­form with the cus­tom­ary ap­proaches facing them in so­cial systems and rela­tion­ships out­side the unit (pro­fes­sional ad­vance­ment and will­ing­ness to con­form to some ex­tent going together)}}and con­trary pres­sure from within the unit itself. This again re­sulted in ten­sion which obliged them to face the need for {{qq|com­mit­ment one way or the other}}. | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{tab}}The posi­tion of the ex­peri­mental ward in­side the frame­work of the large hos­pital prompted the growth of fan­tastic and dis­torted at­ti­tudes towards the unit in the minds of senior staff mem­bers work­ing out­side it; this in­dic­ated the deep chal­lenge which the new ap­proach made to their more tradi­tional con­cepts. For ex­ample an in­cid­ent one night, in which an hyster­ical girl pa­tient was helped back to her ward by a male friend was {{qq|pro­cessed}} by the com­mun­ica­tions system until in its final form, it had become a case of at­tempted sexual as­sault. | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{tab}}An As­sess­ment of the suc­cess of the {{qq|anti{{-}}hos­pital}} in terms of {{qq|results}} (usu­ally meas­ured in such cases by the in­cid­ence of re{{-}}ad­mis­sion) would not be any more mean­ing­ful than a judge­ment on Summer­hill based simply on the pupil{{s}} suc­cess rate in public exam­ina­tions. The cri­terion of re{{-}}ad­mis­sion rates is also in­ad­equate in that staff en­cour­aged pa­tients to return after dis­charge if they felt that a return to the unit would be of value to them. Never­the­less, even by this stand­ard the {{qq|anti{{-}}hos­pital}} re­sults com­pare fa­vour­ably with those achieved by more widely ac­cepted methods{{dash}}17 per cent of pa­tients being re{{-}}ad­mitted during a one{{-}}year period fol­low­ing dis­charge. In the issue of the ''{{w|British Med­ical Journal|The_BMJ}}'' which in­cluded these re­sults Dr. Cooper stated his belief that the ex­peri­ment has estab­lished {{qq|at least {{p|370}}a ''prima facie'' case for rad­ical re­vision of the thera­peutic strat­egy em­ployed in most units for schizo­phrenia}}.<ref>''{{w|British Med­ical Journal|The_BMJ}}'', No. 5476, p. 1462.</ref> | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{tab}}As a post­script to the fore­go­ing, I can deal only sketch­ily with an in­triguing aspect of the work of the British ex­ist­en­tial­ists{{dash}}their ideas on the nature of {{qq|madness}} itself. A re­cur­rent theme in R. D. Laing{{s}} writ­ing is his em­phasis on the dis­astrously narrow field of ex­peri­ence which is cred­ited in con­tempor­ary life, as {{qq|real­ity}}. {{qq|We are far more out of touch with even the near­est ap­proaches of the in­fin­ite reaches of inner space, than we now are with the reaches of outer space. … We are so out of touch with this realm that many people can now argue seri­ously that it does not exist.}}<ref>{{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}}, {{qq|What is Schizo­phrenia?}}, {{popup|op. cit.|opere citato: cited above}}</ref> It is no sur­prise that Dr. Laing has spoken on the power of the drug {{w|LSD|Lysergic_acid_diethylamide}} to ex­tend the bound­aries of real­ity for those who make use of it re­spons­ibly. In ''The Divided Self'' he cites the value of the {{w|Proph­etic Books|William_Blake's_prophetic_books}} of {{w|William Blake|William_Blake}} and (in ''The Self and Others'') re­lates Blake to his pre­vi­ous de­scrip­tion of a {{qq|psy­chotic}}: {{qq|Blake{{s}} posi­tion seems to me to have been this. Single {{q|vision}} (one mod­al­ity of ex­peri­ence) is death. This is what most people regard as san­ity.}} He also charts in this book and in other art­icles, the dual­ism im­plicit in the idea of fantasy to be found in most psycho{{-}}ana­lytic works and in the minds of a good many psy­chi­atrists: {{qq|A very con­fused dual­istic philo­sophy of psy­chical and phys­ical, inner and outer, mental and phys­ical.}} It is the opin­ion of Laing and Cooper that what is clin­ic­ally de­scribed as {{qq|a schizo­phrenic break­down}} may be the onset in the indi­vidual of a voyage into the world of inner space and time. The word {{qq|inner}} is mis­lead­ing, sug­gest­ing a place loc­ated {{qq|inside}} the person; as they use the word it refers to {{qq|our own per­sonal idiom of ex­peri­encing our bodies, other people, the anim­ate and in­anim­ate world: imagin­ation, dreams, fantasy …}}. And far from being a {{qq|dis­ease}} this pro­cess, or {{qq|voyage}}, may well be the path to greater aware­ness, the crisis of the indi­vidual{{s}} strug­gle to real­ise him­self as a person, even{{dash}}the onset of san­ity! (Dr. Cooper has sug­gested that it may be {{qq|when people start to become sane that they enter the mental hos­pital}}). A person under­go­ing this ex­peri­ence may well be {{qq|dif­fi­cult for others}} and is in need of special care{{dash}}but not {{qq|treat­ment}} in {{qq|the quite bizar­rely in­con­gru­ous con­text of the mental hos­pital}}. Those who care for him should as­sume the role of guides{{dash}}and people cap­able of pro­vid­ing this help will very prob­ably be those who have them­selves been through similar ex­peri­ences: {{qq|We need a place where people who have trav­elled further and, con­sequently, may be more lost than psy­chi­atrists and other sane people, can find their way ''further'' into inner space and time, and back again … the person will be guided with full so­cial en­cour­age­ment and sanc­tion into inner space and time, by people who have been there and back again. Psy­chi­atric­ally, this would appear as ex{{-}}pa­tients help­ing future pa­tients go mad.}}<ref>ibid.</ref> | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{tab}}No fully auto­nomous unit in which this pro­cess can take place exists at the present moment,{{ref|3dagger|†††}} but we can de­duce from the {{qq|anti{{-}}{{p|371}}hos­pital}} ex­peri­ment, a good deal about what is re­quired for its suc­cess­ful<!-- 'sucessful' in original --> real­isa­tion. | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | '''CRITICISM AND CONCLUSIONS''' | ||
----- | ----- | ||
− | <font size="2">{{hang|{{note|aster|*}} See ''The Divided Self'', pp. 41-42. For an ac­count of the con­sequences of the ob­struc­tion of this oc­cur­rence: {{qq|an ex­ist­en­tially dead child}} see p. 183. In ''{{l|Views|https://lccn.loc.gov/sf83002178}}'', No. 8, {{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_( | + | <font size="2">{{hang|{{note|aster|*}} See ''The Divided Self'', pp. 41-42. For an ac­count of the con­sequences of the ob­struc­tion of this oc­cur­rence: {{qq|an ex­ist­en­tially dead child}} see p. 183. In ''{{l|Views|https://lccn.loc.gov/sf83002178}}'', No. 8, {{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}} writes: {{qq|… the begin­ning of per­sonal de­velop­ment is never pure passiv­ity. … From the first moment of mother-<wbr>child inter­action, where each is an­other to the other, the child is in the posi­tion of having to ini­ti­ate the pro­ject to become who­ever he is to be, and this is in prin­ciple a free choice, his free crea­tion of his essen­tial nature.}} |
{{note|aster2|**}}<!-- single asterisk in original --> An art­icle in {{w|''The Observer''|The_Observer}} ({{popup|4.9.66|4 September 1966}}) an­nounced the forma­tion of {{qq|Pro­ject 70}}{{dash}}{{qq|a plan to rescue men­tally normal old people from the wards of mental hos­pitals.}} | {{note|aster2|**}}<!-- single asterisk in original --> An art­icle in {{w|''The Observer''|The_Observer}} ({{popup|4.9.66|4 September 1966}}) an­nounced the forma­tion of {{qq|Pro­ject 70}}{{dash}}{{qq|a plan to rescue men­tally normal old people from the wards of mental hos­pitals.}} | ||
Line 145: | Line 173: | ||
{{note|2dagger|††}}<!-- single asterisk in original --> See also Laing{{s}} inter­preta­tion of the state­ments of a schizo­phrenic from the ori­ginal ac­count in {{w|Kraepelin|Emil_Kraepelin}}{{s}} {{l|''Lec­tures on Clin­ical Psy­chi­atry''|https://archive.org/details/lecturesonclini00kraegoog}}, 1905 (pp. 29-31 ''The Divided Self''). Laing writes: {{qq|What does this pa­tient seem to be doing? Surely he is carry­ing on a dia­logue between his own par­od­ied ver­sion of Kraepelin, and his own defi­ant rebel­ling self. {{q|You want to know that too? I tell you who is being meas­ured and is meas­ured and shall be meas­ured. I know all that, and I could tell you, but I do not want to}}.}} Laing com­ments: {{qq|This seems to be plain enough talk.}} | {{note|2dagger|††}}<!-- single asterisk in original --> See also Laing{{s}} inter­preta­tion of the state­ments of a schizo­phrenic from the ori­ginal ac­count in {{w|Kraepelin|Emil_Kraepelin}}{{s}} {{l|''Lec­tures on Clin­ical Psy­chi­atry''|https://archive.org/details/lecturesonclini00kraegoog}}, 1905 (pp. 29-31 ''The Divided Self''). Laing writes: {{qq|What does this pa­tient seem to be doing? Surely he is carry­ing on a dia­logue between his own par­od­ied ver­sion of Kraepelin, and his own defi­ant rebel­ling self. {{q|You want to know that too? I tell you who is being meas­ured and is meas­ured and shall be meas­ured. I know all that, and I could tell you, but I do not want to}}.}} Laing com­ments: {{qq|This seems to be plain enough talk.}} | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{note|3dagger|†††}}<!-- single asterisk in original --> Since this was written an art­icle has ap­peared. {{qq|Schizo­phrenia as a way of life}}, by Ruth Abel (''{{w|Guardian|The_Guardian}}'', {{popup|4.10.66|4 October 1966}}), de­scrib­ing a {{qq|fully auto­nomous unit}} for {{qq|schizo­phrenics}} estab­lished by Drs. Laing, Esterson and Cooper at {{w|Kingsley Hall|Kingsley_Hall}} in London. This pro­ject is fin­anced by {{w|The Phila­delphia As­so­ci­a­tion|Philadelphia_Association}} and it seems that two new centres have been opened during the last few months in {{w|North London|North_London}}, and it is hoped that these are only the first of {{qq|a chain of com­mun­ities}}. | ||
}}</font> | }}</font> | ||
Revision as of 23:23, 2 August 2017
an introduction to
existential analysis
Dr. Laing has written that his main intellectual indebtedness is to “the existential tradition”—
In anarchy 44 J.-P. Sartre is referred to as “one of the foremost anarchist moralists” (Ian Vine: “The Morality of Anarchism”). This description compares intriguingly with another, made by the socialist Alasdair MacIntyre, reviewing Sartre’s book The Problem of Method in Peace News. He refers to Sartre as a newly found “spokesman of genius” for “ersatz bolsheviks” and “imitation anarchists”. Not knowing MacIntyre’s idea of the genuine article, this does not exactly rule the Frenchman out and I believe his work may well justify a place on an anarchist’s book list. Writing with particular reference to Sartre’s recent work, MacIntyre notes that Sartre can offer no bonds, other than reciprocally threatened violence and terror, of sufficient strength to maintain the cohesion of human groups in a world of “impossibly individualist individuals”. Perhaps a spokesman for Stirnerites? Nevertheless, the potentialities of Sartre’s philosophy as a basis for anarchism are incidental to my purpose here.
The first of four episodes of this essay are intended to create a setting against which existential analysis may be viewed.
“Man cannot be sometimes slave and sometimes free; he is wholly and forever free, or he is not free at all.”
Sartre argues against the Freudian three-
R. D. Laing has written that “only by the most outrageous violation of ourselves have we achieved our capacity to live in relative adjustment to a civilisation apparently driven to its own destruction” and has described the “normal” person in the present age as “a half-
“In the context of our present madness that we call normality, sanity, freedom, all our frames of reference are ambiguous and equivocal.”
By far the largest group is the third—
“Many of us, for quite some time have considered that problems of punishment and repression are most acute in the context of imprisonment. But this is not so; the really intractable problem in this sphere is that of the mental hospital.”
In his account of “de-institutionalisation” (anarchy 4) Colin Ward referred to the prison as “the most sinister of institutions” and no doubt it is. But as anarchists are aware, the state can make skilful use of the “approved” concepts of crime and criminality to divert attention from its own more grandiose but identical activities: so we should be alert to the possibility that the institutions openly labelled as prisons are not the only ones serving that function. Suppose, as Roger Moody says in his article that mental hospital and prison are “different terms for the same thing”? If there is some truth in this there is consequently an additional danger in that anything called a “hospital” has automatically a protective cocoon around it as a result of its claim to provide therapy. But surely the “voluntary” presence of many of the patients in mental hospitals ensures that they cannot have a punitive character or effect? A different approach is suggested by the American sociologist Erving Goffman: “… We must see the mental hospital, in the recent historical context in which it developed, as one among a network of institutions designed to provide a residence for various categories of socially troublesome people.”[16]
As Malatesta noted in his essay “Anarchy”, “Organs and functions are inseparable terms. Take from an organ its function, and either the organ will die, or the function will reinstate itself.” The existence of the mental hospital is justified by its function of curing the mentally ill. “The patient’s presence in the hospital is taken as prima facie evidence that he is mentally ill, since the hospitalization of these persons is what the institution is for.” A very common answer to a patient who claims he is sane is the statement: “If you aren’t sick you wouldn’t be in the hospital.”[18] One consequence of this for the person initiated into a “career” as a mental patient is that his past life will be restructured in terms of a “case history”—
Because society needs lunatics to provide it with reassurance of its own sanity, so it has need of institutions to contain them. But as with prisons, the real enemy is not the material structure—
“In the popular mind the schizophrenic is the proto-typical madman—
One psycho-analytic view is that schizophrenia is the outcome of a split between a person’s “conscious” and “subconscious” forces which in the normal state are believed to work simultaneously. Another idea—
This I hope is enough to provide some basis for R. D. Laing’s and A. Esterson’s statement in the introduction to Sanity, Madness and the Family that there is no more disputed condition in the whole field of medicine. “The one thing certain about schizophrenia is that it is a diagnosis, that is a clinical label, applied by some people to others.”[24] The essentially social process which results ultimately in the fixing of this label to one person is the underlying theme of three books and a good many articles by Dr. Laing and his colleagues. I shall try to outline their account of this process subsequently, but an idea of their truly radical conclusions can be given here:
“We do not use the term ‘schizophrenia’ to denote any identifiable condition which we believe exists ‘in’ one person.”[25]
“I do not myself believe that there is any such ‘condition’ as schizophrenia. …”[26]
“Schizophrenia is not a disease in one person but rather a crazy“Schizophrenia, if it means anything, is a more or less characteristic mode of disturbed group behaviour. There are no schizophrenics.”[28]
“Over the last two decades there has been a growing dissatisfaction with any theory or study of the individual which artificially isolates him from the context of his life, interpersonal and social.”
Sartre holds that all groups are structured against an awareness of a “spectator”. This “spectator” may be an individual—
The British existentialists make use of two words, series and nexus, in differentiating between kinds of group—
Praxis and process are both terms used by Sartre. Basically, praxis is what is done by someone: “deeds done by doers”, “the acts of an individual or group”; whilst process refers to “what just happens”, activity not intended by anyone and of which no one person in a group may be aware.
The position of the person within the group will affect his idea of himself—
Dr. Laing’s second book The Self and Others deals with the way in which a person is affected by his situation in a “nexus” of others, in particular within the family. “The others either can contribute to the person’s self-fulfilment, or they can be a potent factor in his losing himself (alienation) even to the point of madness.” He asserts his belief that “fantasy is a mode of experience” and that relationships on a fantasy level are “as basic to all human relatedness as the interactions that most people most of the time are more aware of.”
What happens in the families of “schizophrenics”? It is important to emphasise that it is not the thesis of these workers that the family rather than the individual is “ill”. A group is not an organism—- “The patient was a good, normal, healthy child; until she gradually began
- “to be bad, to do or say things that caused great distress, and which were on the whole ‘put down’ to naughtiness or badness, until
- “this went beyond all tolerable limits so that she could only be regarded as completely mad.”
What was seen by the mother as her daughter’s “good” period, in infancy and early childhood, she described with such remarks as “she gave no trouble”, “she always did what she was told”. Laing comments that what to the mother were signs of goodness, were signs that the child had never been permitted to become “existentially alive”—
In Sanity, Madness and the Family (the first volume of an uncompleted study) Drs. Laing and Esterson present extracts from interviews with members of 11 families, all of which contained daughters diagnosed as “schizophrenic”. In the Introduction to this book the authors write “… we believe that we show that the experience and behaviour of schizophrenics is much more socially intelligible than has come to be supposed by most psychiatrists … we believe that the shift of point of view that these descriptions both embody and demand has an historical significance no less radical than the shift from a demonological to a clinical viewpoint 300 years ago.” Behaviour which is eventually interpreted by the family as a sign of madness is, they argue, the outward expression of a desperate attempt on the part of the “mad one” to “make sense of a senseless situation”—
These writers claim, and I think demonstrate, that armed with a knowledge of the patient’s existential situation, it is possible to make sense of what “psychiatrists still by and large regard as nonsense”. For example, Julie, the patient in “The Ghost of the Weed Garden” referred to herself whilst in her “psychotic” state as “Mrs. Taylor” and as a “tolled bell”. Dr. Laing interprets her chosen title “Mrs. Taylor” as expressing the feelings: “I’m tailor made; I’m a tailored maid; I was made, fed, clothed and tailored” and a “tolled bell” is also “the told belle” “the girl who always did what she was told”. The schizophrenic’s “delusions” of persecution are real expressions of reaction in response to real persecution and are existentially true; that is to say they are “literally true statements within the terms of reference of the individual who makes them.”††
The person is now launched on a “career” as a mental patient. He is confirmed in this role by society’s agents the psychiatrists, in collusion with the patient’s family, and by process of betrayal and degradation[34] becomes an inmate of a mental hospital, which institution embodies “a social structure which in many respects reduplicates the maddening peculiarities of the patient’s family … he finds psychiatrists, administrators, nurses who are his veritable parents, brothers, sisters, who play an interpersonal game which only too often resembles in the intricacies of its rules the game he failed in at home.”[35]
The existential analysts have asserted that a great deal of what passes for treatment in mental institutions is violence. Perhaps we can now begin to see what is meant by this. David Cooper in his article in Views, No. 8 quotes Sartre’s definition of violence: “The corrosive
THEORIES IN PRACTICE: “THE ANTI-HOSPITAL”
In his pamphlet Youth for Freedom (1951) Tony Gibson wrote to the effect that the chief value of Summerhill to the community lay in its having taken the general concept of what a school should be and turned it on its head. Dr. David Cooper’s unit in a large mental hospital “just north-west of London” has done very much the same thing to the general concept of the asylum. To maintain the educational parallel, Dr. Cooper’s experiment (judging from his account of it in New Society[37] also has great relevance for those who would wish to attack the violence implicit in the customary methods of social organisation in schools.
The unit—
The programme during the first year was highly structured, with daily meetings of the whole staff-patient group, separate and regular staff meetings, occupational therapy and organised recreational activity. No “physical” treatments were used except for the occasional dose of mild tranquilliser, and there was no individual psycho-therapy; there were however regular “interviews” between therapist and patient and therapist and patient with various members of his family. After about a year, the staff became dissatisfied with the rigidities of the system and changes in the direction of greater fluidity were felt to be appropriate.
Dr. Cooper writes of two areas in which the consequent “destructuring” had remarkable effects—
The workers in the unit were faced with conflicting pressures—
The position of the experimental ward inside the framework of the large hospital prompted the growth of fantastic and distorted attitudes towards the unit in the minds of senior staff members working outside it; this indicated the deep challenge which the new approach made to their more traditional concepts. For example an incident one night, in which an hysterical girl patient was helped back to her ward by a male friend was “processed” by the communications system until in its final form, it had become a case of attempted sexual assault.
An Assessment of the success of the “anti-hospital” in terms of “results” (usually measured in such cases by the incidence of re-admission) would not be any more meaningful than a judgement on Summerhill based simply on the pupil’s success rate in public examinations. The criterion of re-admission rates is also inadequate in that staff encouraged patients to return after discharge if they felt that a return to the unit would be of value to them. Nevertheless, even by this standard the “anti-hospital” results compare favourably with those achieved by more widely accepted methods— As a postscript to the foregoing, I can deal only sketchily with an intriguing aspect of the work of the British existentialists—
CRITICISM AND CONCLUSIONS
** An article in The Observer (4.9.66) announced the formation of “Project 70”—
*** This may be an allusion to a case which was receiving some publicity at that time. Zenya Belov, a student, was confined in a Russian mental institution around September, 1965—
† References to a letter from Brenda Jordan in Peace News (17.6.66).
†† See also Laing’s interpretation of the statements of a schizophrenic from the original account in Kraepelin’s Lectures on Clinical Psychiatry, 1905 (pp. 29-31 The Divided Self). Laing writes: “What does this patient seem to be doing? Surely he is carrying on a dialogue between his own parodied version of Kraepelin, and his own defiant rebelling self. ‘You want to know that too? I tell you who is being measured and is measured and shall be measured. I know all that, and I could tell you, but I do not want to’.” Laing comments: “This seems to be plain enough talk.”
††† Since this was written an article has appeared. “Schizophrenia as a way of life”, by Ruth Abel (Guardian, 4.10.66), describing a “fully autonomous unit” for “schizophrenics” established by Drs. Laing, Esterson and Cooper at Kingsley Hall in London. This project is financed by The Philadelphia Association and it seems that two new centres have been opened during the last few months in North London, and it is hoped that these are only the first of “a chain of communities”.
David Cooper, “Sartre on Genet”, New Left Review, No. 25.
R. D. Laing, The Politics of Experience and the Bird of Paradise, Penguin Books, Autumn, 1966.
R. D. Laing, H. Phillipson, A. R. Lee, Interpersonal Perception: A Theory and a Method, London, Tavistock, 1966.
T. S. Szasz, The Myth of Mental Illness, London, Seeker and Warburg, 1962.
Carl R. Rogers, On Becoming a Person, London, Constable & Co., 1961.
<references>
- ↑ Robert G. Olson, An Introduction to Existentialism, New York, Dover Publications, 1962, p. 52.
- ↑ ibid., p. 105 (a reference to an episode in Being and Nothingness, p. 495).
- ↑ J.-P. Sartre, Situations III, Paris, Gallimard, 1949 (quoted by Olson, p. 121).
- ↑ Olson, op. cit., p. 119.
- ↑ J.-P. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, London, Methuen, 1956, pp. 461-2.
- ↑ ibid., pp. 471-75 (quoted by Olson, p. 121).
- ↑ The first part of R. D. Laing’s The Self and Others is a lucid argument against the basic concepts of traditional psycho-
analysis. - ↑ “Massacre of the Innocents”, Peace News, 22nd January, 1965.
- ↑ BBC “Panorama” on “Mental Health”, 6th June, 1966.
- ↑ David Cooper, “The Anti-Hospital: An Experiment in Psychiatry”, New Society, 11th March, 1965.
- ↑ David Cooper, “Violence in Psychiatry”, Views, No. 8, Summer, 1965.
- ↑ ibid.
- ↑ Part of a letter by Pierre-Joseph Brie, “Insanity and the Egg”, Peace News, 1st July, 1966.
- ↑ T. S. Szasz, “Politics and Mental Health”, American Journal of Psychiatry, No. 115 (1958) (quoted by Erving Goffman in Asylums, p. 509).
- ↑ Erving Goffman, <span data-html="true" class="plainlinks" title="Wikipedia: Asylums—
Essays on the Social Situation of Mental Patients and Other Inmates">Asylums— Essays on the Social Situation of Mental Patients and Other Inmates, New York, Anchor Books, 1961, pp. 363-4. - ↑ ibid., p. 354.
- ↑ ibid., p. 135.
- ↑ ibid., p. 380.
- ↑ For a reconstruction of a psychiatric interrogation see “The Case Conference”, Views, No. 11, Summer, 1966. <span data-html="true" class="plainlinks" title="Wikipedia: Elias Canetti<!-- 'Elia Canetti' in original -->">Elias Canetti<!-- 'Elia Canetti' in original --> has written that “questioning is a forcible intrusion. When used as an instrument of power, it is like a knife cutting into the flesh of the victim. … The most blatant tyranny is the one that asks the most questions” (Crowds and Power, Gollancz, 1962).
- ↑ A sentence of Dr. Joshua Dierer’s, speaking at the World Federation of Mental Health, 1960 (quoted by Colin Ward in “Where The Shoe Pinches”, anarchy 4).
- ↑ Goffman, op. cit., p. 384.
- ↑ An estimate made by the Swiss psychiatrist E. Bleuler, quoted by David Cooper in “The Anti-Hospital”.
- ↑ P. Rube, “Healing Process in Schizophrenia”, Journal of Nervous and Mental Diseases, 1948 (quoted by John Linsie in “Schizophrenia: A Social Disease”, anarchy 24).
- ↑ R. D. Laing, “What is Schizophrenia?”, New Left Review, No. 28.
- ↑ R. D. Laing and A. Esterson, Sanity, Madness and the Family, London, Tavistock, 1964.
- ↑ R. D. Laing, “What is Schizophrenia?”, op. cit.
- ↑ David Cooper, “The Anti-Hospital”, op. cit.
- ↑ David Cooper, Violence in Psychiatry, Views, No. 8.
- ↑ R. D. Laing, “Us and Them”, Views, No. 11.
- ↑ R. D. Laing and A. Esterson, op. cit.
- ↑ R. D. Laing, “Us and Them”, op. cit.
- ↑ David Cooper, “Two Types of Rationality”, New Left Review, No. 29.
- ↑ op. cit., p. 155.
- ↑ Erving Goffman in Asylums makes use of the term “career” to denote “the social strand” of a person’s life inaugurated at the moment of his definition as a mental patient; “betrayal funnel” to describe the circuit of figures (relatives, psychiatrists, etc.) whose interactions end with the patient’s confinement in the 374asylum, and “degradation ceremonial” for the psychiatric examination preceding the patient’s admission.
- ↑ David Cooper, “Violence in Psychiatry”, op. cit.
- ↑ ibid.
- ↑ New Society, 11th March, 1965.
- ↑ British Medical Journal, No. 5476, p. 1462.
- ↑ R. D. Laing, “What is Schizophrenia?”, op. cit.
- ↑ ibid.