Difference between revisions of "Anarchy 70/Libertarian Psychiatry: an introduction to existential analysis"
(One intermediate revision by the same user not shown) | |||
Line 15: | Line 15: | ||
− | {{p|s1}}{{sc|This art­icle aims to draw at­ten­tion}} to the work of a group of British psy­chi­atrists of whom the best known are {{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}} and {{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}}. They have achieved some no­tori­ety in this country because of the ex­tent of their di­ver­gence, both in theory and prac­tice, from cur­rent psy­chi­atric ortho­doxy—and par­tic­u­larly as a con­sequence of their refer­ences to the pre­val­ent {{qq|treat­ment}} of the men­tally ill as {{qq|viol­ence}}. As a teacher, I am not qual­ified to at­tempt more than an out­line of their ideas as under­stood by me, after read­ing their books and art­icles and some related studies. But the im­plica­tions of the work of the British ex­ist­en­tial­ist group ex­tend beyond the limits of psy­chi­atry—and the very gener­ality of their as­ser­tions in­vites a re­sponse from the layman. Writing of the pro­cess which in their view results in the ul­ti­mate in­val­id­a­tion of persons through the label­ling of them as {{qq|mad}}, Laing asks: {{qq| | + | {{p|s1|n}}{{sc|This art­icle aims to draw at­ten­tion}} to the work of a group of British psy­chi­atrists of whom the best known are {{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}} and {{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}}. They have achieved some no­tori­ety in this country because of the ex­tent of their di­ver­gence, both in theory and prac­tice, from cur­rent psy­chi­atric ortho­doxy—and par­tic­u­larly as a con­sequence of their refer­ences to the pre­val­ent {{qq|treat­ment}} of the men­tally ill as {{qq|viol­ence}}. As a teacher, I am not qual­ified to at­tempt more than an out­line of their ideas as under­stood by me, after read­ing their books and art­icles and some related studies. But the im­plica­tions of the work of the British ex­ist­en­tial­ist group ex­tend beyond the limits of psy­chi­atry—and the very gener­ality of their as­ser­tions in­vites a re­sponse from the layman. Writing of the pro­cess which in their view results in the ul­ti­mate in­val­id­a­tion of persons through the label­ling of them as {{qq|mad}}, Laing asks: {{qq|{{e|l}}what func­tion does this pro­ced­ure serve for the civic order? These ques­tions are only begin­ning to be asked, much less answered. {{e}} So­cially, this work must now move to further under­stand­ing {{e}} of the mean­ing of all this within the larger con­text of the civic order of so­ciety—that is, of the ''polit­ical'' order, of the ways persons exer­cise control and power over one an­other.}} (''{{w|New Left Review|New_Left_Review}}'', No. 28.) Anarch­ism is about just this, and any theory, from what­ever dis­cipline, which leads to a ques­tion­ing of the polit­ical order of so­ciety should have rel­ev­ance for us—and we should know some­thing about it. |
{{tab}}Dr. Laing has written that his main intel­lec­tual in­debt­ed­ness is to {{qq|the {{w|ex­ist­en­tial|Existentialism|Existentialism}} tradi­tion}}—{{w|Kierke­gaard|Søren_Kierkegaard|Søren Kierkegaard}}, {{w|Jaspers|Karl_Jaspers|Karl Jaspers}}, {{w|Heideg­ger|Martin_Heidegger|Martin Heidegger}}, {{w|Bins­wanger|Ludwig_Binswanger|Ludwig Binswanger}}, {{w|Tillich|Paul_Tillich|Paul Tillich}} and {{w|Sartre|Jean-Paul_Sartre|Jean-Paul Sartre}}—and of these there is no doubt that Sartre{{s}} in­flu­ence has been the great­est. The British ana­lysts have clearly worked out their own the­or­et­ical basis and in many in­stan­ces have de­veloped Sartre{{s}} ideas rather than merely adopted them as they stand. I am not cer­tain, for ex­ample, how com­pletely Laing and Cooper share Sartre{{s}} total re­jec­tion of the con­cept of {{qq|the un­con­scious}}. However, their book {{l|''Reason and Viol­ence'': ''A Decade of Sartre{{s}} Philo­sophy'' 1950-1960|http://laingsociety.org/biblio/randv.htm|Full text at the Laing Society}} (Tavistock, 1964) opens with a com­pli­ment­ary pre­fat­ory note from the French philo­sopher—I believe this is an un­usual honour for a book about his ideas—and this ''im­prim­atur'' sug­gests that what­ever their diver­gen­cies, they can­not be basic. | {{tab}}Dr. Laing has written that his main intel­lec­tual in­debt­ed­ness is to {{qq|the {{w|ex­ist­en­tial|Existentialism|Existentialism}} tradi­tion}}—{{w|Kierke­gaard|Søren_Kierkegaard|Søren Kierkegaard}}, {{w|Jaspers|Karl_Jaspers|Karl Jaspers}}, {{w|Heideg­ger|Martin_Heidegger|Martin Heidegger}}, {{w|Bins­wanger|Ludwig_Binswanger|Ludwig Binswanger}}, {{w|Tillich|Paul_Tillich|Paul Tillich}} and {{w|Sartre|Jean-Paul_Sartre|Jean-Paul Sartre}}—and of these there is no doubt that Sartre{{s}} in­flu­ence has been the great­est. The British ana­lysts have clearly worked out their own the­or­et­ical basis and in many in­stan­ces have de­veloped Sartre{{s}} ideas rather than merely adopted them as they stand. I am not cer­tain, for ex­ample, how com­pletely Laing and Cooper share Sartre{{s}} total re­jec­tion of the con­cept of {{qq|the un­con­scious}}. However, their book {{l|''Reason and Viol­ence'': ''A Decade of Sartre{{s}} Philo­sophy'' 1950-1960|http://laingsociety.org/biblio/randv.htm|Full text at the Laing Society}} (Tavistock, 1964) opens with a com­pli­ment­ary pre­fat­ory note from the French philo­sopher—I believe this is an un­usual honour for a book about his ideas—and this ''im­prim­atur'' sug­gests that what­ever their diver­gen­cies, they can­not be basic. | ||
− | {{tab}}In [[Anarchy 44|{{sc|anarchy}} 44]] J.-P. Sartre is re­ferred to as {{qq|one of the fore­most anarch­ist moral­ists}} ([[Author:Ian Vine|Ian Vine]]: {{qq|[[Anarchy 44/The morality of anarchism|The Moral­ity of Anarch­ism]]}}). This de­scrip­tion com­pares in­triguingly with an­other, made by the so­cial­ist {{w|Alasdair<!-- 'Alisdair' in original --> MacIntyre|Alasdair_MacIntyre|Alasdair MacIntyre}}, re­view­ing Sartre{{s}} book ''{{w|The Prob­lem of Method|Search_for_a_Method|Search for a Method}}'' in ''{{w|Peace News|Peace_News}}''. He re­fers to Sartre as a newly found {{qq|spokes­man of genius}} for {{qq|ersatz {{w|bolshev­iks|Bolsheviks|Bolsheviks}}}} and {{qq|im­it­a­tion anarch­ists}}. Not know­ing MacIntyre{{s}} idea of the genu­ine art­icle, this does not ex­actly rule the French­man out and I believe his work may well just­ify a place on an anarch­ist{{s}} book list. Writing with par­tic­u­lar refer­ence to Sartre{{s}} recent work, MacIntyre notes that Sartre can offer no bonds, other than re­cip­roc­ally threat­ened viol­ence and terror, of suf­fi­cient strength to main­tain the co­he­sion of human groups in a world of {{qq|im­pos­sibly indi­vidual­ist indi­viduals}}. Per­haps a spokes­man for {{w|Stirner­ites|Philosophy_of_Max_Stirner|Philosophy of Max Stirner}}? Never­the­less, the poten­ti­alit­ies of Sartre{{s}} philo­sophy as a basis for anarch­ism are in­cid­ental to my pur­pose here. | + | {{tab}}In [[Anarchy 44|{{sc|anarchy}} 44]] J.-P. Sartre is re­ferred to as {{qq|one of the fore­most {{p|354}}anarch­ist moral­ists}} ([[Author:Ian Vine|Ian Vine]]: {{qq|[[Anarchy 44/The morality of anarchism|The Moral­ity of Anarch­ism]]}}). This de­scrip­tion com­pares in­triguingly with an­other, made by the so­cial­ist {{w|Alasdair<!-- 'Alisdair' in original --> MacIntyre|Alasdair_MacIntyre|Alasdair MacIntyre}}, re­view­ing Sartre{{s}} book ''{{w|The Prob­lem of Method|Search_for_a_Method|Search for a Method}}'' in ''{{w|Peace News|Peace_News}}''. He re­fers to Sartre as a newly found {{qq|spokes­man of genius}} for {{qq|ersatz {{w|bolshev­iks|Bolsheviks|Bolsheviks}}}} and {{qq|im­it­a­tion anarch­ists}}. Not know­ing MacIntyre{{s}} idea of the genu­ine art­icle, this does not ex­actly rule the French­man out and I believe his work may well just­ify a place on an anarch­ist{{s}} book list. Writing with par­tic­u­lar refer­ence to Sartre{{s}} recent work, MacIntyre notes that Sartre can offer no bonds, other than re­cip­roc­ally threat­ened viol­ence and terror, of suf­fi­cient strength to main­tain the co­he­sion of human groups in a world of {{qq|im­pos­sibly indi­vidual­ist indi­viduals}}. Per­haps a spokes­man for {{w|Stirner­ites|Philosophy_of_Max_Stirner|Philosophy of Max Stirner}}? Never­the­less, the poten­ti­alit­ies of Sartre{{s}} philo­sophy as a basis for anarch­ism are in­cid­ental to my pur­pose here. |
{{tab}}The first of four epis­odes of this essay are in­tended to create a set­ting against which ex­ist­en­tial ana­lysis may be viewed. | {{tab}}The first of four epis­odes of this essay are in­tended to create a set­ting against which ex­ist­en­tial ana­lysis may be viewed. | ||
− | {{p|s2}}'''EXISTENTIAL FREEDOM''' | + | {{p|s2|n}}'''EXISTENTIAL FREEDOM''' |
Line 32: | Line 32: | ||
− | {{tab}}The con­cept of free­dom at the core of ex­ist­en­tial­ism is very dif­fer­ent from what I take to be the com­mon under­stand­ing of the term. In gen­eral usage, a man is free in as much as he can achieve his chosen ends with a min­imum of effort. Simil­arly, a man{{s}} free­dom is re­duced as the ob­stacles between his de­sires and chosen ends are in­creased. Free­dom is re­garded as a measur­able quant­ity; one may have a lot or a little of it, and it can be taken away—or even {{qq|given}}. The anarch­ist{{s}} hypo­thet­ical destin­a­tion, the {{qq|free}} so­ciety, may often be thought of in the sense of an har­mo­ni­ous envir­on­ment in which all re­mov­able ob­stacles between man{{s}} de­sires and their ful­fil­ment have been elim­in­ated. But for Sartre, man is totally free by reason of his very being as man, and ob­stacles between de­sires and chosen ends are of no rel­ev­ance. To use a favoured ex­ist­en­tial­ist phrase, man is free by onto­lo­gical neces­sity. But his free­dom rests, within this con­cept, in his total re­spons­ibil­ity in the face of un­deter­mined choice and in his recog­ni­tion of the in­escap­able ob­lig­a­tion to choose. An intuit­ive aware­ness of this re­spons­ib­il­ity—per­haps pro­voked by some sort of {{qq|ex­treme situ­a­tion}}—gives rise to what Sartre calls {{qq|the anguish of free­dom}}. It is our fate to be free. {{qq| | + | {{tab}}The con­cept of free­dom at the core of ex­ist­en­tial­ism is very dif­fer­ent from what I take to be the com­mon under­stand­ing of the term. In gen­eral usage, a man is free in as much as he can achieve his chosen ends with a min­imum of effort. Simil­arly, a man{{s}} free­dom is re­duced as the ob­stacles between his de­sires and chosen ends are in­creased. Free­dom is re­garded as a measur­able quant­ity; one may have a lot or a little of it, and it can be taken away—or even {{qq|given}}. The anarch­ist{{s}} hypo­thet­ical destin­a­tion, the {{qq|free}} so­ciety, may often be thought of in the sense of an har­mo­ni­ous envir­on­ment in which all re­mov­able ob­stacles between man{{s}} de­sires and their ful­fil­ment have been elim­in­ated. But for Sartre, man is totally free by reason of his very being as man, and ob­stacles between de­sires and chosen ends are of no rel­ev­ance. To use a favoured ex­ist­en­tial­ist phrase, man is free by onto­lo­gical neces­sity. But his free­dom rests, within this con­cept, in his total re­spons­ibil­ity in the face of un­deter­mined choice and in his recog­ni­tion of the in­escap­able ob­lig­a­tion to choose. An intuit­ive aware­ness of this re­spons­ib­il­ity—per­haps pro­voked by some sort of {{qq|ex­treme situ­a­tion}}—gives rise to what Sartre calls {{qq|the anguish of free­dom}}. It is our fate to be free. {{qq|{{e|l}}One must always de­cide for one­self and efforts to shift the burden of re­spons­ib­il­ity upon others are neces­sar­ily self-de­feat­ing. Not to choose is also to choose, for even if we de­liver our power of de­ci­sion to others, we are still re­spons­ible for having done so. It is always the indi­vidual who de­cides that others will choose for him.}}<ref>Robert G. Olson, ''An Intro­duc­tion to Ex­ist­en­tial­ism'', New York, Dover Publi­ca­tions, 1962, p. 52.</ref> In so far as we are free in our choices, we {{qq|create}} the ob­stacles that lie between our pro­ject and its ful­fil­ment: {{qq|an in­sig­ni­fic­ant public of­fi­cial in {{w|Mont-de-Marsan|Mont-de-Marsan}} without means may not have the op­por­tun­ity to go to {{w|New York|New_York_City|New York City}} if that be his ambi­tion. But the ob­stacles which stand in his way would not exist as ob­stacles were it not for his free choice of values: in this case, his desire to go {{p|355}}to New York.}}<ref>ibid., p. 105 (a refer­ence to an epis­ode in ''Being and No­thing­ness'', p. 495).</ref> Even though human free­dom, in his view, is total, Sartre ad­mits of a sense in which it may be spoken of in terms of degree. A man may be said to become {{qq|more free}} as his con­scious­ness of total free­dom and re­spons­ib­il­ity in­creases; and cer­tain situ­a­tions in life can crystal­lize this aware­ness. In an ap­par­ently cryptic para­graph in ''Being and No­thing­ness'' Sartre de­scribes the {{w|German Oc­cupa­tion of France|German_military_administration_in_occupied_France_during_World_War_II|German military administration in occupied France during World War II}} during the last {{w|war|World_War_II|World War II}} as such a situ­a­tion. {{qq|{{e|l}}the choice that each of us made of his life and his being was an au­then­tic choice because it was made face to face with death, because it could always have been ex­pressed in these terms: {{q|Rather death than{{e|r}}}}.}}<ref>{{w|J.-P. Sartre|Jean-Paul_Sartre|Jean-Paul Sartre}}, ''Situations III'', Paris, Gallimard, 1949 (quoted by {{popup|Olson|Robert G. Olson. An Introduction to Existentialism.}}, p. 121).</ref> But the issue is not just one of an in­creased sense of re­spons­ib­il­ity for our day-to-day options—for in­stance in de­cid­ing upon a change in oc­cu­pa­tion, or merely which book to read next; most sig­ni­fic­antly ''we choose our­selves'', and our day-to-day de­ci­sions neces­sarily re­flect this primary choice we have made. We are what we have chosen to be. All our sub­sequent modes of action are re­lated to this original {{qq|project-of-being}}, {{qq|Freely chosen at the moment one wrenches one­self away from the in-itself to create one{{s}} own world}}<ref>{{popup|Olson|Robert G. Olson}}, {{popup|op. cit.|opere citato: cited above}}, p. 119.</ref> (the in-itself: the world of things). This event I take to be com­par­able with what R. D. Laing calls {{qq|ex­ist­en­tial birth}} which, he sug­gests, is as essen­tial for a fully human ex­ist­ence as the bio­lo­gical birth which it nor­mally follows.{{ref|aster|*}} It is only in rela­tion to this funda­mental choice, the indi­vidual{{s}} original {{qq|pro­ject-of-being}} that his later beha­viour can be fully under­stood. The plaus­ibil­ity of this basic idea is not in­creased by Sartre{{s}} denial of the divi­sion of the self into con­scious and un­con­scious modes; the idea of a tooth­less infant con­sciously de­termin­ing its future life­style and pur­pose is at first thought ab­surd. But whilst ex­pli­citly deny­ing valid­ity to the {{qq|un­con­scious}} Sartre does separ­ate con­scious­ness into {{qq|re­flect­ive}} and {{qq|non-re­flect­ive}} levels, and it is at the non-re­flect­ive level that this funda­mental choice is made. He stresses that this original choice is in no way de­liber­ate: {{qq|This is not because it would be less con­scious or less ex­plicit than a de­liber­a­tion but, on the con­trary, because it is the found­a­tion of all de­liber­a­tion and because {{e}} a de­liber­a­tion re­quires an inter­pret­a­tion in terms of an original choice.}}<ref>{{w|J.-P. Sartre|Jean-Paul_Sartre|Jean-Paul Sartre}}, {{w|''Being and No­thing­ness''|Being_and_Nothingness}}, London, Methuen, 1956, pp. 461-2.</ref> The con­cepts of {{qq|au­then­ti­city}} and its ap­proxim­ate op­po­site {{qq|bad-faith}} are in a sense under­stand­able as judge­ments (al­though Sartre claims only to use these terms de­script­ively) upon the degree of con­cord­ance between the choices of our re­flect­ive con­scious­ness and our original pro­ject-of-being. In a pas­sage which bears di­rectly upon ex­ist­en­tial ana­lysis he writes that a man {{qq|can make vol­un­tary de­ci­sions which are op­posed to the funda­mental ends which he has chosen. These de­ci­sions can be only vol­un­tary—that is, re­flect­ive. {{e}} Thus, for ex­ample, I can de­cide to cure myself of {{w|stutter­ing|Stuttering|Stuttering}}. I can even {{p|256}}suc­ceed in it. {{e}} In fact I can ob­tain a result by using merely tech­nical methods. {{e}} But these re­sults will only dis­place the in­firm­ity from which I suf­fer; an­other will arise in its place and will in its own way ex­press the total end which I pur­sue. {{e}} It is the same with these cures as it is with the cure of {{w|hys­teria|Hysteria|Hysteria}} by {{w|elec­tric shock treat­ment|Electroconvulsive_therapy|Electroconvulsive therapy}}. We know that this ther­apy can effect the dis­ap­pear­ance of an hys­terical con­trac­tion of the leg, but as one will see some time later the con­trac­tion will ap­pear in the arm. This is because the hys­teria can be cured only as a total­ity, for it is a total pro­ject of the for-itself}}<ref>ibid., pp. 471-75 (quoted by {{popup|Olson|Robert G. Olson}}, p. 121).</ref> (the for-itself: the world of con­scious­ness and in­ten­tion). |
{{tab}}Sartre argues against the {{w|Freud­ian|Sigmund_Freud|Sigmund Freud}} three-way split of the per­sonal­ity into {{w|id, ego and super-ego|Id,_ego_and_super-ego|Id, ego and super-ego}} and the {{w|psycho{{-}}ana­lytic|Psychoanalysis|Psychoanalysis}} dictum of con­scious beha­viour as de­term­ined by drives, in­stincts and de­sires al­legedly eman­at­ing from the id. As Sartre{{s}} argu­ments hinge upon his stated belief in man{{s}} on­to­lo­gical free­dom, Freud{{s}} pro­ject of {{qq|de­term­ina­tion by the un­con­scious}} is met with similar ob­jec­tions to those made against other de­term­in­ist theories and I need not at­tempt to sum­mar­ise them here.<ref>The first part of {{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}}{{s}} ''The Self and Others'' is a lucid argu­ment against the basic con­cepts of tradi­tional psycho-ana­lysis.</ref> The only valid form of ther­apy is one aimed at dis­cover­ing an indi­vidual{{s}} funda­mental pro­ject-of-being—and this is the pur­pose of ex­ist­en­tial ana­lysis (or psycho-ana­lysis; the pre­fix seems to be op­tional). {{qq|The prin­ciple of this psycho-ana­lysis is that man is a total­ity and not a col­lec­tion; he there­fore ex­presses him­self in his total­ity in the most in­sig­ni­fic­ant and the most super­fi­cial as­pects of his con­duct}} (''Being and No­thing­ness''). Through the use of a tech­nique or method based on such as­sump­tions the ini­tially {{qq|crazy}} actions of the in­sane may be made com­pre­hens­ible—and may even ap­pear {{qq|reason­able}} if a picture of the world in which the pa­tient lives can be as­sembled. | {{tab}}Sartre argues against the {{w|Freud­ian|Sigmund_Freud|Sigmund Freud}} three-way split of the per­sonal­ity into {{w|id, ego and super-ego|Id,_ego_and_super-ego|Id, ego and super-ego}} and the {{w|psycho{{-}}ana­lytic|Psychoanalysis|Psychoanalysis}} dictum of con­scious beha­viour as de­term­ined by drives, in­stincts and de­sires al­legedly eman­at­ing from the id. As Sartre{{s}} argu­ments hinge upon his stated belief in man{{s}} on­to­lo­gical free­dom, Freud{{s}} pro­ject of {{qq|de­term­ina­tion by the un­con­scious}} is met with similar ob­jec­tions to those made against other de­term­in­ist theories and I need not at­tempt to sum­mar­ise them here.<ref>The first part of {{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}}{{s}} ''The Self and Others'' is a lucid argu­ment against the basic con­cepts of tradi­tional psycho-ana­lysis.</ref> The only valid form of ther­apy is one aimed at dis­cover­ing an indi­vidual{{s}} funda­mental pro­ject-of-being—and this is the pur­pose of ex­ist­en­tial ana­lysis (or psycho-ana­lysis; the pre­fix seems to be op­tional). {{qq|The prin­ciple of this psycho-ana­lysis is that man is a total­ity and not a col­lec­tion; he there­fore ex­presses him­self in his total­ity in the most in­sig­ni­fic­ant and the most super­fi­cial as­pects of his con­duct}} (''Being and No­thing­ness''). Through the use of a tech­nique or method based on such as­sump­tions the ini­tially {{qq|crazy}} actions of the in­sane may be made com­pre­hens­ible—and may even ap­pear {{qq|reason­able}} if a picture of the world in which the pa­tient lives can be as­sembled. | ||
Line 39: | Line 39: | ||
− | {{p|s3}}'''THE INSANE IN A MAD WORLD''' | + | {{p|s3|n}}'''THE INSANE IN A MAD WORLD''' |
Line 47: | Line 47: | ||
− | {{tab}}In 1965 there were 160,000 people in mental hos­pitals in Britain and an estim­ated 200,000 psy­chotics in the com­mun­ity. Nearly half of all hos­pital beds are oc­cu­pied by the men­tally ill. In a tele­vision pro­gramme on mental health<ref>{{w|BBC}} {{qq|{{w|Panorama|Panorama_(TV_series)}}}} on {{qq|Mental Health}}, 6th June, 1966.</ref> the number of the men­tally ill in Britain was given as half a million. The tele­vised psy­chi­atrist sug­gested that there were four main cat­egor­ies of ill­ness: people with mental de­form­ity, {{p|357}}old people with {{qq|mental equip­ment in de­cline}} ( | + | {{tab}}In 1965 there were 160,000 people in mental hos­pitals in Britain and an estim­ated 200,000 psy­chotics in the com­mun­ity. Nearly half of all hos­pital beds are oc­cu­pied by the men­tally ill. In a tele­vision pro­gramme on mental health<ref>{{w|BBC}} {{qq|{{w|Panorama|Panorama_(TV_series)}}}} on {{qq|Mental Health}}, 6th June, 1966.</ref> the number of the men­tally ill in Britain was given as half a million. The tele­vised psy­chi­atrist sug­gested that there were four main cat­egor­ies of ill­ness: people with mental de­form­ity, {{p|357}}old people with {{qq|mental equip­ment in de­cline}} ({{e}} per­haps old people with no­where else to go?{{ref|aster2|**}}), people with physiolo­gic­ally normal mental equip­ment but with ac­quired neur­otic pat­terns, and lastly, vic­tims of {{qq|bio{{-}}chem­ical ill­ness}}—in his words, {{qq|Struck down out of the blue}}. This fourth cat­egory per­haps re­flects, more than any­thing else, the cur­rently fa­voured styles of treat­ment! |
− | {{tab}}By far the largest group is the third—the {{qq|neur­otics and psychot­ics}}. Among these {{qq|{{w|schizo­phrenia|Schizophrenia|Schizophrenia}}}} is the most common dia­gnosis. {{qq|In most European coun­tries about one per cent of the popu­la­tion go to hos­pital at least once in their life­time with the dia­gnosis schizo­phrenia.}}<ref>{{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}}, {{qq|The Anti{{-}}Hos­pital: An Ex­peri­ment in Psy­chi­atry}}, {{w|''New So­ciety''|New_Society}}, 11th March, 1965.</ref> But what mean­ing can be given to these stat­istics and as­sess­ments without a stand­ard of san­ity or mad­ness? {{qq|Defin­i­tions of mental health pro­pounded by the ex­perts usually re­duce to the no­tion of con­form­ism, to a set of more or less ar­bit­rar­ily pos­ited so­cial norms. | + | {{tab}}By far the largest group is the third—the {{qq|neur­otics and psychot­ics}}. Among these {{qq|{{w|schizo­phrenia|Schizophrenia|Schizophrenia}}}} is the most common dia­gnosis. {{qq|In most European coun­tries about one per cent of the popu­la­tion go to hos­pital at least once in their life­time with the dia­gnosis schizo­phrenia.}}<ref>{{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}}, {{qq|The Anti{{-}}Hos­pital: An Ex­peri­ment in Psy­chi­atry}}, {{w|''New So­ciety''|New_Society}}, 11th March, 1965.</ref> But what mean­ing can be given to these stat­istics and as­sess­ments without a stand­ard of san­ity or mad­ness? {{qq|Defin­i­tions of mental health pro­pounded by the ex­perts usually re­duce to the no­tion of con­form­ism, to a set of more or less ar­bit­rar­ily pos­ited so­cial norms.{{e|r}}}}<ref>{{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}}, {{qq|Viol­ence in Psy­chi­atry}}, ''{{l|Views|https://lccn.loc.gov/sf83002178|Library of Congress catalogue entry}}'', No. 8, Summer, 1965.</ref> The label­ling of people as mad can have the so­cial func­tion of defin­ing the area of {{qq|san­ity}}—per­haps there is a par­al­lel with {{w|Durkheim|Émile_Durkheim|Émile Durkheim}}{{s}} theory of crime and pun­­ish­ment as {{qq|neces­sary}} to re­spect­able so­ciety to mark off the limits of per­mis­sible and toler­ated beha­viour. {{qq|So­ciety needs lun­at­ics in order that it may regard itself as sane.}}<ref>ibid.</ref> It could also be argued that cer­tain kinds of so­ciety {{qq|need}} lun­at­ics as their man­agers; a dis­cus­sion in {{w|''Peace News''|Peace_News}} re­cently was con­cerned with the un­certi­fi­able mad­ness of the {{w|Amer­ican Presid­ent|Lyndon_B._Johnson|Lyndon B. Johnson}} in rela­tion to a {{qq|col­lect­ive norm of in­san­ity}}. A cor­re­spond­ent noted: {{qq|No sig­ni­fic­ant mem­ber of a power estab­lish­ment can ever be {{q|cert­ifi­ably in­sane}} since it is this same estab­lish­ment which de­ter­mines the defin­i­tions of {{q|san­ity}} and {{q|in­san­ity}} and which de­cides—checked only by the oc­ca­sional con­science of an oc­ca­sional pro­fes­sional medi­cal man—when {{q|in­san­ity}} becomes {{q|{{w|cert­ifi­able|Involuntary_commitment|Involuntary commitment}}}}.}}<ref>Part of a letter by Pierre{{-}}Joseph Brie, {{qq|In­san­ity and the Egg}}, {{w|''Peace News''|Peace_News}}, 1st July, 1966.</ref> |
− | {{tab}}In offi­cial stat­istics there must, in any case, be a murky over­lap area between what comes out as {{qq|crime}} and what as {{qq|lunacy}}—and a lot of luck in who ends up in which in­stitu­tion. Per­haps it is the in­stitu­tional bureau­cracy that has most need of the labels: {{qq|Ac­cord­ing to the common­sense defin­i­tion,}} writes Dr. Theodore Szasz, {{qq|mental health is the abil­ity to play what­ever the game of so­cial living might con­sist of and to play it well. Con­versely, to re­fuse to play, or to play badly, means that the person is men­tally ill. The ques­tion may now be raised as to what are the dif­fer­ences, if any, between so­cial non­con­form­ity (or devi­a­tion) and mental ill­ness. Leaving tech­nical psy­chi­atric con­sider­a­tions aside for the moment, I shall argue that the dif­fer­ence between these two no­tions—as ex­pressed for ex­ample by the state­ments {{q|He is wrong}} and {{q|He is men­tally ill}}—does not lie in any ob­serv­able ''facts'' to which they may point, but may con­sist only of a dif­fer­ence in our ''at­ti­tudes'' toward our sub­ject.}}<ref>{{w|T. S. Szasz|Thomas_Szasz|Thomas Szasz}}, {{qq|Polit­ics and Mental Health}}, {{w|''Amer­ican Journal of Psy­chi­atry''|American_Journal_of_Psychiatry}}, No. 115 (1958) (quoted by {{w|Erving Goffman|Erving_Goffman}} in {{w|''Asylums''|Asylums_(book)|Asylums (book)}}, p. 509).</ref> What sort of be­ha­viour is likely to lead those with the ap­propri­ate at­ti­tudes to see signs of mental ill­ness and to set going the trans­fer pro­cess from {{p|358}}{{qq|person to pa­tient}}? {{qq|Ordin­arily the patho­logy which first draws at­ten­tion to the pa­tient{{s}} con­di­tion is con­duct that is {{q|in­ap­propri­ate in the situ­a­tion}}. | + | {{tab}}In offi­cial stat­istics there must, in any case, be a murky over­lap area between what comes out as {{qq|crime}} and what as {{qq|lunacy}}—and a lot of luck in who ends up in which in­stitu­tion. Per­haps it is the in­stitu­tional bureau­cracy that has most need of the labels: {{qq|Ac­cord­ing to the common­sense defin­i­tion,}} writes Dr. Theodore Szasz, {{qq|mental health is the abil­ity to play what­ever the game of so­cial living might con­sist of and to play it well. Con­versely, to re­fuse to play, or to play badly, means that the person is men­tally ill. The ques­tion may now be raised as to what are the dif­fer­ences, if any, between so­cial non­con­form­ity (or devi­a­tion) and mental ill­ness. Leaving tech­nical psy­chi­atric con­sider­a­tions aside for the moment, I shall argue that the dif­fer­ence between these two no­tions—as ex­pressed for ex­ample by the state­ments {{q|He is wrong}} and {{q|He is men­tally ill}}—does not lie in any ob­serv­able ''facts'' to which they may point, but may con­sist only of a dif­fer­ence in our ''at­ti­tudes'' toward our sub­ject.}}<ref>{{w|T. S. Szasz|Thomas_Szasz|Thomas Szasz}}, {{qq|Polit­ics and Mental Health}}, {{w|''Amer­ican Journal of Psy­chi­atry''|American_Journal_of_Psychiatry}}, No. 115 (1958) (quoted by {{w|Erving Goffman|Erving_Goffman}} in {{w|''Asylums''|Asylums_(book)|Asylums (book)}}, p. 509).</ref> What sort of be­ha­viour is likely to lead those with the ap­propri­ate at­ti­tudes to see signs of mental ill­ness and to set going the trans­fer pro­cess from {{p|358}}{{qq|person to pa­tient}}? {{qq|Ordin­arily the patho­logy which first draws at­ten­tion to the pa­tient{{s}} con­di­tion is con­duct that is {{q|in­ap­propri­ate in the situ­a­tion}}. {{e}} Further, since in­ap­propri­ate beha­viour is typic­ally beha­viour that some­one does not like and finds ex­tremely trouble­some, deci­sions con­cern­ing it tend to be polit­ical, in the sense of ex­pres­sing the spe­cial inter­ests of some par­tic­u­lar fac­tion or person.{{e|r}}}}<ref>{{w|Erving Goffman|Erving_Goffman}}, ''{{w|Asylums—Essays on the So­cial Situ­a­tion of Mental Pa­tients and Other In­mates|Asylums_(book)|Asylums (book)}}'', New York, Anchor Books, 1961, pp. 363-4.</ref> As an ex­ample of {{qq|in­ap­propri­ate beha­viour}}, con­sider the case of {{qq|The Naked Prisoner}} ({{sc|{{w|freedom|Freedom_(newspaper)|Freedom (newspaper)}}}}, 16.10.65). Mr. Paul Pawlowski was ar­rested during a demon­stra­tion at the {{w|Spanish Embassy|Embassy_of_Spain,_London|Embassy of Spain, London}} in {{w|London}}. Eventu­ally reach­ing {{w|Brixton Prison|HM_Prison_Brixton|HM Prison Brixton}}, he re­fused to put on the stand­ard pris­on­er{{s|r}} uni­form and was con­sequently locked up, naked, in his cell. Thus he re­mained for ten days. On the tenth day he was inter­viewed by a so­cial worker: {{qq|{{e|l}}You know that two doctors have seen you while you have been in Brixton {{e}} they came to the con­clu­sion that what you need is a little stay in a mental hos­pital.}} In fact he did not have the benefit of this con­fine­ment. The hos­pital psy­chi­atrist de­cided that Mr. Pawlowski{{s}} opin­ions were not those of the ma­jor­ity but {{qq|people are not put into mental hos­pitals for their opin­ions. They do that sort of thing in {{w|Russia|Soviet_Union|Soviet Union}}.}}{{ref|aster3|***}} Mr. Pawlowski was for­tun­ate in his psy­chi­atrist, but it is inter­est­ing to see how the pre{{-}}exist­ing at­ti­tudes of offi­cials brought him to the brink of ad­mis­sion. The overt polit­ical im­plica­tions may make this ex­ample ex­cep­tional—but it would not seem to be to the ad­vant­age of a person sus­pected of mental ill­ness to have been {{qq|mixed up in polit­ics}} or {{qq|the dregs of so­ciety in {{w|CND|Campaign_for_Nuclear_Disarmament|Campaign for Nuclear Disarmament}}}}—which it seems, may well be taken as a con­firm­atory symp­tom.{{ref|dagger|†}} The mental health service—like the edu­ca­tion {{qq|service}}—is a func­tional part of the present so­cial system and, as such, acts to pre­serve that system and its values. {{qq|The psy­chi­atric pro­fes­sion is a bureau­cracy,}} writes James Green, a con­trib­utor to ''{{l|Views|https://lccn.loc.gov/sf83002178|Library of Congress catalogue entry}}'', No. 8, {{qq|making an es­sen­tial con­trib­u­tion to the run­ning of gov­ern­ment and ad­minis­tra­tion. {{e}} Most psy­chi­atrists would prob­ably take for granted the struc­ture and values of their own so­ciety, in such a way that the thera­peutic pro­cess becomes a ques­tion of re­turn­ing the sick person to his so­cial con­text or roles, e.g. his family, whether or not this is good for him, and without ques­tion­ing whether the con­text and roles are them­selves satis­fact­ory.}} Al­though no doubt un­repre­sent­at­ive and redol­ent of {{qq|what they do in Russia}} I can­not resist quot­ing the words of a psy­chi­atrist par­ti­cipant in a re­cently tele­vised dis­cus­sion: {{qq|Our func­tion is to get people well enough to be in­doc­trin­ated.}} It would be mis­lead­ing to sug­gest that any­thing but a tiny minor­ity become in­mates of asylums simply or only because they hold dis­ap­proved {{p|359}}opin­ions, but pos­sibly such cases may lead to a con­sider­a­tion of the far more subtle {{qq|polit­ical}} and so­cial mean­ing of the label­ling and con­fine­ment of the un­vocal ma­jor­ity. |
− | {{p|s4}}'''CURATIVE—OR PUNITIVE?''' | + | {{p|s4|n}}'''CURATIVE—OR PUNITIVE?''' |
Line 62: | Line 62: | ||
− | {{tab}}In his ac­count of {{qq|[[Anarchy 4/Where the shoe pinches|de{{-}}in­sti­tu­tion­al­isa­tion]]}} ([[Anarchy 4|{{sc|anarchy}} 4]]) [[Author:Colin Ward|Colin Ward]] re­ferred to the prison as {{qq|the most sin­is­ter of in­sti­tu­tions}} and no doubt it is. But as anarch­ists are aware, the state can make skil­ful use of the {{qq|ap­proved}} con­cepts of crime and crim­in­ality to di­vert at­ten­tion from its own more grandi­ose but identical activ­it­ies: so we should be alert to the pos­si­bil­ity that the in­sti­tu­tions openly la­belled as prisons are not the only ones serving that func­tion. Sup­pose, as Roger Moody says in his art­icle that mental hos­pital and prison are {{qq|dif­fer­ent terms for the same thing}}? If there is some truth in this there is con­sequently an ad­di­tional danger in that any­thing called a {{qq|hos­pital}} has auto­mat­ic­ally a pro­tect­ive cocoon around it as a result of its claim to pro­vide ther­apy. But surely the {{qq|volun­tary}} presence of many of the pa­tients in mental hos­pitals en­sures that they can­not have a pun­it­ive char­acter or ef­fect? A dif­fer­ent ap­proach is sug­gested by the Amer­ican so­ci­olo­gist {{w|Erving Goffman|Erving_Goffman}}: {{qq| | + | {{tab}}In his ac­count of {{qq|[[Anarchy 4/Where the shoe pinches|de{{-}}in­sti­tu­tion­al­isa­tion]]}} ([[Anarchy 4|{{sc|anarchy}} 4]]) [[Author:Colin Ward|Colin Ward]] re­ferred to the prison as {{qq|the most sin­is­ter of in­sti­tu­tions}} and no doubt it is. But as anarch­ists are aware, the state can make skil­ful use of the {{qq|ap­proved}} con­cepts of crime and crim­in­ality to di­vert at­ten­tion from its own more grandi­ose but identical activ­it­ies: so we should be alert to the pos­si­bil­ity that the in­sti­tu­tions openly la­belled as prisons are not the only ones serving that func­tion. Sup­pose, as Roger Moody says in his art­icle that mental hos­pital and prison are {{qq|dif­fer­ent terms for the same thing}}? If there is some truth in this there is con­sequently an ad­di­tional danger in that any­thing called a {{qq|hos­pital}} has auto­mat­ic­ally a pro­tect­ive cocoon around it as a result of its claim to pro­vide ther­apy. But surely the {{qq|volun­tary}} presence of many of the pa­tients in mental hos­pitals en­sures that they can­not have a pun­it­ive char­acter or ef­fect? A dif­fer­ent ap­proach is sug­gested by the Amer­ican so­ci­olo­gist {{w|Erving Goffman|Erving_Goffman}}: {{qq|{{e|l}}We must see the mental hos­pital, in the re­cent histor­ical con­text in which it de­veloped, as one among a net­work of in­sti­tu­tions de­signed to pro­vide a res­id­ence for vari­ous cat­egor­ies of so­cially trouble­some people.}}<ref>ibid., p. 354.</ref> |
{{tab}}Goffman states that only a small number of pa­tients enter mental hos­pital will­ingly, in the sense that they believe it will be good for them, having come to see them­selves as {{qq|men­tally un­bal­anced}}—and as Laing and Cooper argue, even in these cases this self{{-}}per­cep­tion as being {{qq|ill}} or {{qq|mad}} can be in­duced by the beha­viour or strat­egy of the person{{s}} im­medi­ate relat­ives and con­tacts. The sequence from {{qq|person to pa­tient}} can follow a series of as­so­ci­ated stages set in mo­tion by a {{qq|com­plain­ant}} who sees an action on the part of the pre{{-}}pa­tient as per­haps a {{qq|last{{-}}straw}} and re­fers him to a suc­ces­sion of {{qq|medi­ators}}—prob­ably drawn from among teach­ers, so­cial workers, clergy, psych­iatrists, law­yers, po­lice—one of whom, with co{{-}}opera­tion from the {{qq|sick}} man{{s}} relat­ives, will com­mit the indi­vidual to hos­pital with legal sanc­tion. {{qq|The so­ciety{{s}} offi­cial view,}} writes Goffman, {{qq|is that in­mates are there because they are suf­fer­ing from mental ill­ness. However, in the degree that the {{q|men­tally ill}} out­side hos­pitals numer­ically ap­proach or sur­pass those inside hos­pitals, one could say that mental pa­tients dis­tinct­ively suf­fer not from mental ill­ness, but from con­tin­gen­cies.}}<ref>ibid., p. 135.</ref> In other words, good or bad luck—de­pend­ing on your point of view. One might debate the degree to which this whole pro­cess is {{qq|volun­tary}}—bear­ing in mind that the indi­vidual is un­pre­pared for the nature of his future life in the hos­pital, is prob­ably living {{p|360}}in so­cially dis­tres­sing circum­stances which would have the ef­fect of making most al­tern­at­ives seem favour­able, and is sub­ject to col­lus­ive pres­sure from both relat­ives and {{qq|medi­ators}}. | {{tab}}Goffman states that only a small number of pa­tients enter mental hos­pital will­ingly, in the sense that they believe it will be good for them, having come to see them­selves as {{qq|men­tally un­bal­anced}}—and as Laing and Cooper argue, even in these cases this self{{-}}per­cep­tion as being {{qq|ill}} or {{qq|mad}} can be in­duced by the beha­viour or strat­egy of the person{{s}} im­medi­ate relat­ives and con­tacts. The sequence from {{qq|person to pa­tient}} can follow a series of as­so­ci­ated stages set in mo­tion by a {{qq|com­plain­ant}} who sees an action on the part of the pre{{-}}pa­tient as per­haps a {{qq|last{{-}}straw}} and re­fers him to a suc­ces­sion of {{qq|medi­ators}}—prob­ably drawn from among teach­ers, so­cial workers, clergy, psych­iatrists, law­yers, po­lice—one of whom, with co{{-}}opera­tion from the {{qq|sick}} man{{s}} relat­ives, will com­mit the indi­vidual to hos­pital with legal sanc­tion. {{qq|The so­ciety{{s}} offi­cial view,}} writes Goffman, {{qq|is that in­mates are there because they are suf­fer­ing from mental ill­ness. However, in the degree that the {{q|men­tally ill}} out­side hos­pitals numer­ically ap­proach or sur­pass those inside hos­pitals, one could say that mental pa­tients dis­tinct­ively suf­fer not from mental ill­ness, but from con­tin­gen­cies.}}<ref>ibid., p. 135.</ref> In other words, good or bad luck—de­pend­ing on your point of view. One might debate the degree to which this whole pro­cess is {{qq|volun­tary}}—bear­ing in mind that the indi­vidual is un­pre­pared for the nature of his future life in the hos­pital, is prob­ably living {{p|360}}in so­cially dis­tres­sing circum­stances which would have the ef­fect of making most al­tern­at­ives seem favour­able, and is sub­ject to col­lus­ive pres­sure from both relat­ives and {{qq|medi­ators}}. | ||
− | {{tab}}As {{w|Malatesta|Errico_Malatesta|Errico Malatesta}} noted in his essay {{qq|{{l|Anarchy|http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/errico-malatesta-anarchy|Full text at the Anarchist Library}}}}, {{qq|Organs and func­tions are in­separ­able terms. Take from an organ its func­tion, and either the organ will die, or the func­tion will re­in­state itself.}} The ex­ist­ence of the mental hos­pital is just­ified by its func­tion of curing the men­tally ill. {{qq|The pa­tient{{s}} pres­ence in the hos­pital is taken as ''{{popup|prima facie|sufficient until proven otherwise}}'' evid­ence that he is men­tally ill, since the hos­pital­iza­tion of these per­sons is what the in­sti­tu­tion is for.}} A very com­mon answer to a pa­tient who claims he is sane is the state­ment: {{qq|If you aren{{t}} sick you wouldn{{t}} be in the hos­pital.}}<ref>ibid., p. 380.</ref> One con­sequence of this for the person ini­tiated into a {{qq|career}} as a mental pa­tient is that his past life will be re­struc­tured in terms of a {{qq|case history}}—and he may be denied rights of pri­vacy over what he pre­vi­ously re­garded as {{qq|his own busi­ness}}—any facet of which may now pro­vide evid­ence of {{qq|symp­toms}}.<ref>For a re­con­struc­tion of a psy­chi­atric inter­roga­tion see {{qq|The Case Con­fer­ence}}, ''{{l|Views|https://lccn.loc.gov/sf83002178|Library of Congress catalogue entry}}'', No. 11, Summer, 1966. {{w|Elias Canetti<!- | + | {{tab}}As {{w|Malatesta|Errico_Malatesta|Errico Malatesta}} noted in his essay {{qq|{{l|Anarchy|http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/errico-malatesta-anarchy|Full text at the Anarchist Library}}}}, {{qq|Organs and func­tions are in­separ­able terms. Take from an organ its func­tion, and either the organ will die, or the func­tion will re­in­state itself.}} The ex­ist­ence of the mental hos­pital is just­ified by its func­tion of curing the men­tally ill. {{qq|The pa­tient{{s}} pres­ence in the hos­pital is taken as ''{{popup|prima facie|sufficient until proven otherwise}}'' evid­ence that he is men­tally ill, since the hos­pital­iza­tion of these per­sons is what the in­sti­tu­tion is for.}} A very com­mon answer to a pa­tient who claims he is sane is the state­ment: {{qq|If you aren{{t}} sick you wouldn{{t}} be in the hos­pital.}}<ref>ibid., p. 380.</ref> One con­sequence of this for the person ini­tiated into a {{qq|career}} as a mental pa­tient is that his past life will be re­struc­tured in terms of a {{qq|case history}}—and he may be denied rights of pri­vacy over what he pre­vi­ously re­garded as {{qq|his own busi­ness}}—any facet of which may now pro­vide evid­ence of {{qq|symp­toms}}.<ref>For a re­con­struc­tion of a psy­chi­atric inter­roga­tion see {{qq|The Case Con­fer­ence}}, ''{{l|Views|https://lccn.loc.gov/sf83002178|Library of Congress catalogue entry}}'', No. 11, Summer, 1966. {{w|Elias Canetti<!-- 'Elia Canetti' in original -->|Elias_Canetti|Elias Canetti}} has written that {{qq|ques­tion­ing is a for­cible in­tru­sion. When used as an in­stru­ment of power, it is like a knife cut­ting into the flesh of the vic­tim. {{e}} The most blat­ant tyranny is the one that asks the most ques­tions}} ({{w|''Crowds and Power''|Crowds_and_Power|Crowds and Power}}, Gollancz, 1962).</ref> Once inside, the pa­tient may find the in­ternal organ­isa­tion of the asylum domin­ated by a {{qq|ward system}} separ­at­ing pa­tients off into {{qq|dis­ease}} cat­egor­ies, the vari­ous levels pro­vid­ing dif­fer­ent stand­ards of ac­com­mod­a­tion, food and grounds{{-}}and{{-}}town {{qq|priv­ileges}}, among other factors of import­ance in the life of the pa­tient. The ma­terial and so­cial pro­vi­sions on each ward level are offi­cially those that are most ap­propri­ate to the mental con­di­tion of the pa­tient. But whilst the system may be just­ified by its par­tis­ans on these grounds, it has an un­ac­know­ledged func­tion as an inmate{{-}}con­trol­ling device. There is a direct par­al­lel here with the al­leged pur­pose of the {{w|stream­ing|Tracking_(education)|Tracking (education)}} system in schools; in­vari­ably de­fended on the basis of its edu­ca­tional value yet actu­ally opera­ting in schools as an im­port­ant com­pon­ent of the dis­ciplin­ary system. And in asylums, as in schools, these {{qq|divide and rule}} dis­ciplin­ary strat­egies have de­veloped as the best method of {{qq|man­age­ment by a small staff of a large number of in­volun­tary in­mates}}. |
{{tab}}Because so­ciety needs luna­tics to pro­vide it with re­as­sur­ance of its own san­ity, so it has need of in­sti­tu­tions to con­tain them. But as with prisons, the real enemy is not the ma­terial struc­ture—{{qq|It is our own anxi­ety which forces us to lock people up}}<ref>A sen­tence of Dr. Joshua Dierer{{s}}, speak­ing at the {{w|World Federa­tion of Mental Health|World_Federation_for_Mental_Health|World Federation for Mental Health}}, 1960 (quoted by [[Author:Colin Ward|Colin Ward]] in {{qq|[[Anarchy 4/Where the shoe pinches|Where The Shoe Pinches]]}}, [[Anarchy 4|{{sc|anarchy}} 4]]).</ref>—and it is through anxi­ety about our own san­ity that we build walls around the {{qq|men­tally ill}}. {{qq|Mental hos­pitals are not found in our so­ciety because super­visors, psych­iatrists and at­tend­ants want jobs; mental hos­pitals are found because there is a market for them. If all the mental hos­pitals in a given region were emptied and closed down today, to­morrow relat­ives, po­lice, and judges would raise a clamour for new ones; and these true clients of the mental hos­pital would de­­mand an in­sti­tu­tion to sat­isfy their needs.}}<ref>Goffman, op. cit., p. 384.</ref> | {{tab}}Because so­ciety needs luna­tics to pro­vide it with re­as­sur­ance of its own san­ity, so it has need of in­sti­tu­tions to con­tain them. But as with prisons, the real enemy is not the ma­terial struc­ture—{{qq|It is our own anxi­ety which forces us to lock people up}}<ref>A sen­tence of Dr. Joshua Dierer{{s}}, speak­ing at the {{w|World Federa­tion of Mental Health|World_Federation_for_Mental_Health|World Federation for Mental Health}}, 1960 (quoted by [[Author:Colin Ward|Colin Ward]] in {{qq|[[Anarchy 4/Where the shoe pinches|Where The Shoe Pinches]]}}, [[Anarchy 4|{{sc|anarchy}} 4]]).</ref>—and it is through anxi­ety about our own san­ity that we build walls around the {{qq|men­tally ill}}. {{qq|Mental hos­pitals are not found in our so­ciety because super­visors, psych­iatrists and at­tend­ants want jobs; mental hos­pitals are found because there is a market for them. If all the mental hos­pitals in a given region were emptied and closed down today, to­morrow relat­ives, po­lice, and judges would raise a clamour for new ones; and these true clients of the mental hos­pital would de­­mand an in­sti­tu­tion to sat­isfy their needs.}}<ref>Goffman, op. cit., p. 384.</ref> | ||
− | {{p|s5}}'''SCHIZOPHRENIA—A PSEUDO{{-}}DISEASE?''' | + | {{p|s5|n}}'''SCHIZOPHRENIA—A PSEUDO{{-}}DISEASE?''' |
Line 79: | Line 79: | ||
− | {{p|361}}{{tab}}The vari­ous titles given to mental dis­eases, says Goffman, serve to meet the needs of hos­pital census regu­la­tions. {{qq|When pressed | + | {{p|361}}{{tab}}The vari­ous titles given to mental dis­eases, says Goffman, serve to meet the needs of hos­pital census regu­la­tions. {{qq|When pressed {{e}} staff will allow that these syn­drome titles are vague and doubt­ful.}} A lot of people at the present time, ap­pear to have schizo­phrenia—this dia­gnosis is ap­plied to two out of three pa­tients in British mental hos­pitals and it has been estim­ated that for every {{qq|schizo­phrenic}} re­ceiv­ing some form of treat­ment there are ten {{qq|un­detec­ted}} in the com­mun­ity.<ref>An estim­ate made by the Swiss psy­chi­atrist {{w|E. Bleuler|Eugen_Bleuler|Eugen Bleuler}}, quoted by {{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}} in {{qq|The Anti{{-}}Hos­pital}}.</ref> |
{{tab}}One psycho{{-}}ana­lytic view is that schizo­phrenia is the out­come of a split between a person{{s}} {{qq|con­scious}} and {{qq|un­con­scious}} forces which in the normal state are believed to work sim­ul­tan­eously. An­other idea—in schizo­phrenia {{qq|there is a subtle change in brain chem­istry which inter­feres in some way with nerve im­pulses.}}<ref>{{popup|P. Rube|Peter Rube}}<!-- according to semanticscholar.org; dubious source -->, {{qq|Heal­ing Pro­cess in Schizo­phrenia}}, ''{{w|Journal of Nervous and Mental Dis­eases|Journal_of_Nervous_and_Mental_Disease|Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease}}'', 1948 (quoted by [[Author:John Linsie|John Linsie]] in {{qq|[[Anarchy 24/Schizophrenia: a social disease|Schizo­phrenia: A So­cial Dis­ease]]}}, [[Anarchy 24|{{sc|anarchy}} 24]]).</ref> The pop­ular­ity of this view and others sim­ilar to it has led to an em­phasis on sur­gical or phys­ical treat­ment such as electro{{-}}con­vuls­ive ther­apy (a low voltage shock passed between the temples) and, in some cases, opera­tions on the brain ({{w|leu­co­tomy|Lobotomy|Lobotomy}} and {{w|lo­botomy|Lobotomy|Lobotomy}}). In at least one London hos­pital schizo­phrenics have been placed in deep freeze. Drugs are much used. And it seems that what are taken to be the symp­toms of the dis­ease can be elim­in­ated by the use of such means at least for a time. As Sartre ob­served, one {{qq|can ob­tain a result by using merely tech­nical methods.}} But, as the writer of a sur­vey in ''The Ob­server'' ({{popup|5.6.66|5 June 1966}}) com­mented: {{qq|No one knows, ex­cept in the fuzzi­est out­line, what the treat­ments do. And none of them is a cure.}} [[Author:John Linsie|John Linsie]] in his [[Anarchy 24/Schizophrenia: a social disease|article]] in [[Anarchy 24|{{sc|anarchy}} 24]] pointed out that the ef­fect­ive­ness of drugs and E.C.T. in tem­por­arily re­moving {{qq|symp­toms}} has per­haps pre­vented more wide­spread re­search into the basic aeti­ology of the {{qq|dis­ease}}. Schizo­phrenia often oc­curs within the same family and some re­search­ers believe that it is trans­mitted ge­net­ic­ally. John Linsie quoted {{w|Mayer{{-}}Gross|Wilhelm_Mayer-Gross|Wilhelm Mayer-Gross}}: {{qq|It may now be re­garded as estab­lished that hered­it­ary factors play a pre­domin­ant role in the causa­tion of schizo­phrenic psy­cho­sis}}—and then trumped this with the opinion of an­other expert, {{w|Roth|Martin_Roth_(psychiatrist)|Martin Roth}}: {{qq|No simple ge­netic hypo­thesis ac­cords with all the facts.}} | {{tab}}One psycho{{-}}ana­lytic view is that schizo­phrenia is the out­come of a split between a person{{s}} {{qq|con­scious}} and {{qq|un­con­scious}} forces which in the normal state are believed to work sim­ul­tan­eously. An­other idea—in schizo­phrenia {{qq|there is a subtle change in brain chem­istry which inter­feres in some way with nerve im­pulses.}}<ref>{{popup|P. Rube|Peter Rube}}<!-- according to semanticscholar.org; dubious source -->, {{qq|Heal­ing Pro­cess in Schizo­phrenia}}, ''{{w|Journal of Nervous and Mental Dis­eases|Journal_of_Nervous_and_Mental_Disease|Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease}}'', 1948 (quoted by [[Author:John Linsie|John Linsie]] in {{qq|[[Anarchy 24/Schizophrenia: a social disease|Schizo­phrenia: A So­cial Dis­ease]]}}, [[Anarchy 24|{{sc|anarchy}} 24]]).</ref> The pop­ular­ity of this view and others sim­ilar to it has led to an em­phasis on sur­gical or phys­ical treat­ment such as electro{{-}}con­vuls­ive ther­apy (a low voltage shock passed between the temples) and, in some cases, opera­tions on the brain ({{w|leu­co­tomy|Lobotomy|Lobotomy}} and {{w|lo­botomy|Lobotomy|Lobotomy}}). In at least one London hos­pital schizo­phrenics have been placed in deep freeze. Drugs are much used. And it seems that what are taken to be the symp­toms of the dis­ease can be elim­in­ated by the use of such means at least for a time. As Sartre ob­served, one {{qq|can ob­tain a result by using merely tech­nical methods.}} But, as the writer of a sur­vey in ''The Ob­server'' ({{popup|5.6.66|5 June 1966}}) com­mented: {{qq|No one knows, ex­cept in the fuzzi­est out­line, what the treat­ments do. And none of them is a cure.}} [[Author:John Linsie|John Linsie]] in his [[Anarchy 24/Schizophrenia: a social disease|article]] in [[Anarchy 24|{{sc|anarchy}} 24]] pointed out that the ef­fect­ive­ness of drugs and E.C.T. in tem­por­arily re­moving {{qq|symp­toms}} has per­haps pre­vented more wide­spread re­search into the basic aeti­ology of the {{qq|dis­ease}}. Schizo­phrenia often oc­curs within the same family and some re­search­ers believe that it is trans­mitted ge­net­ic­ally. John Linsie quoted {{w|Mayer{{-}}Gross|Wilhelm_Mayer-Gross|Wilhelm Mayer-Gross}}: {{qq|It may now be re­garded as estab­lished that hered­it­ary factors play a pre­domin­ant role in the causa­tion of schizo­phrenic psy­cho­sis}}—and then trumped this with the opinion of an­other expert, {{w|Roth|Martin_Roth_(psychiatrist)|Martin Roth}}: {{qq|No simple ge­netic hypo­thesis ac­cords with all the facts.}} | ||
Line 87: | Line 87: | ||
{{tab}}{{qq|We do not use the term {{q|schizo­phrenia}} to de­note any iden­ti­fi­able condi­tion which we believe exists {{q|in}} one person.}}<ref>{{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}} and {{w|A. Esterson|Aaron_Esterson|Aaron Esterson}}, ''San­ity, Mad­ness and the Family'', London, Tavi­stock, 1964.</ref> | {{tab}}{{qq|We do not use the term {{q|schizo­phrenia}} to de­note any iden­ti­fi­able condi­tion which we believe exists {{q|in}} one person.}}<ref>{{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}} and {{w|A. Esterson|Aaron_Esterson|Aaron Esterson}}, ''San­ity, Mad­ness and the Family'', London, Tavi­stock, 1964.</ref> | ||
− | {{tab}}{{qq|I do not myself believe that there is any such {{q|condi­tion}} as schizo­phrenia. | + | {{tab}}{{qq|I do not myself believe that there is any such {{q|condi­tion}} as schizo­phrenia.{{e|r}}}}<ref>{{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}}, {{qq|What is Schizo­phrenia?}}, {{popup|op. cit.|opere citato: cited above}}</ref> |
− | {{tab}}{{qq|Schizo­phrenia is not a dis­ease in one person but rather a crazy {{p|362}}way in which whole famil­ies func­tion. | + | {{tab}}{{qq|Schizo­phrenia is not a dis­ease in one person but rather a crazy {{p|362}}way in which whole famil­ies func­tion.{{e|r}}}}<ref>{{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}}, {{qq|The Anti-Hos­pital}}, {{popup|op. cit.|opere citato: cited above}}</ref> |
{{tab}}{{qq|Schizo­phrenia, if it means any­thing, is a more or less char­ac­ter­istic mode of dis­turbed group beha­viour. ''There are no schizo­phrenics.''}}<ref>{{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}}, Viol­ence in Psy­chi­atry, ''{{l|Views|https://lccn.loc.gov/sf83002178|Library of Congress catalogue entry}}'', No. 8.</ref> | {{tab}}{{qq|Schizo­phrenia, if it means any­thing, is a more or less char­ac­ter­istic mode of dis­turbed group beha­viour. ''There are no schizo­phrenics.''}}<ref>{{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}}, Viol­ence in Psy­chi­atry, ''{{l|Views|https://lccn.loc.gov/sf83002178|Library of Congress catalogue entry}}'', No. 8.</ref> | ||
− | {{p|s6}}'''THE FAMILY—{{qq|FROM GOOD TO BAD TO MAD}}''' | + | {{p|s6|n}}'''THE FAMILY—{{qq|FROM GOOD TO BAD TO MAD}}''' |
Line 110: | Line 110: | ||
{{tab}}Praxis and pro­cess are both terms used by Sartre. Basic­ally, praxis is what is done by some­one: {{qq|deeds done by doers}}, {{qq|the acts of an indi­vidual or group}}; whilst pro­cess re­fers to {{qq|what just hap­pens}}, activ­ity not in­tended by any­one and of which no one person in a group may be aware. | {{tab}}Praxis and pro­cess are both terms used by Sartre. Basic­ally, praxis is what is done by some­one: {{qq|deeds done by doers}}, {{qq|the acts of an indi­vidual or group}}; whilst pro­cess re­fers to {{qq|what just hap­pens}}, activ­ity not in­tended by any­one and of which no one person in a group may be aware. | ||
− | {{tab}}The posi­tion of the person within the group will af­fect his idea of him­self—of who he is. In the same way his view of others in the group af­fects their defin­i­tions of them­selves. And again, his beha­viour will be af­fected by his idea of what other people make of him. As a person moves during even one day, from group to group, from one mode of as­so­ci­a­tion to an­other, he must adapt him­self to each con­text: {{qq|Each group re­quires more or less rad­ical in­ternal trans­forma­tion of the per­sons who com­prise it. Con­sider the meta­morph­oses that the one man may go through in one day | + | {{tab}}The posi­tion of the person within the group will af­fect his idea of him­self—of who he is. In the same way his view of others in the group af­fects their defin­i­tions of them­selves. And again, his beha­viour will be af­fected by his idea of what other people make of him. As a person moves during even one day, from group to group, from one mode of as­so­ci­a­tion to an­other, he must adapt him­self to each con­text: {{qq|Each group re­quires more or less rad­ical in­ternal trans­forma­tion of the per­sons who com­prise it. Con­sider the meta­morph­oses that the one man may go through in one day {{e}} family man, speck of crowd dust, func­tion­ary in the organ­isa­tion, friend. These are not simply dif­fer­ent roles: each is a whole past and present and future, of­fer­ing dif­fer­ing op­tions and con­straints, dif­fer­ent degrees of change or iner­tia, dif­fer­ent kinds of close­ness and dis­tance, dif­fer­ent sets of rights and ob­liga­tions, dif­fer­ent pledges and pro­mises.}}<ref>{{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}}, {{qq|Us and Them}}, {{popup|op. cit.|opere citato: cited above}}</ref> |
{{tab}}Dr. Laing{{s}} second book ''{{w|The Self and Others|Self_and_Others|Self and Others}}'' deals with the way in which a person is af­fected by his situ­ation in a {{qq|nexus}} of others, in par­tic­u­lar within the family. {{qq|The others either can con­trib­ute to the per­son{{s}} self{{-}}ful­fil­ment, or they can be a potent factor in his losing him­self (ali­en­a­tion) even to the point of mad­ness.}} He as­serts his belief that {{qq|fantasy is a mode of ex­peri­ence}} and that rela­tion­ships on a fantasy level are {{qq|as basic to all human rela­ted­ness as the inter­ac­tions that most people most of the time are more aware of.}} | {{tab}}Dr. Laing{{s}} second book ''{{w|The Self and Others|Self_and_Others|Self and Others}}'' deals with the way in which a person is af­fected by his situ­ation in a {{qq|nexus}} of others, in par­tic­u­lar within the family. {{qq|The others either can con­trib­ute to the per­son{{s}} self{{-}}ful­fil­ment, or they can be a potent factor in his losing him­self (ali­en­a­tion) even to the point of mad­ness.}} He as­serts his belief that {{qq|fantasy is a mode of ex­peri­ence}} and that rela­tion­ships on a fantasy level are {{qq|as basic to all human rela­ted­ness as the inter­ac­tions that most people most of the time are more aware of.}} | ||
Line 122: | Line 122: | ||
What was seen by the mother as her daugh­ter{{s}} {{qq|good}} period, in infancy and early child­hood, she de­scribed with such re­marks as {{qq|she gave no trouble}}, {{qq|she always did what she was told}}. Laing com­ments that what to the mother were signs of good­ness, were signs that the child had never been per­mit­ted to become {{qq|ex­ist­en­tially alive}}—in fact {{qq|being ex­ist­en­tially dead re­ceives the high­est com­menda­tion}}. The {{qq|bad}} period was the time of ad­oles­cence, during which the pa­tient made her great­est strug­gle towards a real­isa­tion of her own self through auto­nom­ous action but found that her ef­forts were con­tinu­ally de­feated by {{qq|the com­plete ab­sence of any­one in her world who could or would see some sense in her point of view}}. The trans­fer from {{qq|bad}} to {{qq|mad}} came as some­thing of a relief to the rest of the family, who {{qq|blamed them­selves for not real­ising sooner}}. As the mother said: {{qq|I knew she really could not have meant the awful things she said to me. In a way, I blame myself but, in a way, I{{m}} glad that it was an ill­ness after all, but if only I had not waited so long before I took her to a doctor.}} | What was seen by the mother as her daugh­ter{{s}} {{qq|good}} period, in infancy and early child­hood, she de­scribed with such re­marks as {{qq|she gave no trouble}}, {{qq|she always did what she was told}}. Laing com­ments that what to the mother were signs of good­ness, were signs that the child had never been per­mit­ted to become {{qq|ex­ist­en­tially alive}}—in fact {{qq|being ex­ist­en­tially dead re­ceives the high­est com­menda­tion}}. The {{qq|bad}} period was the time of ad­oles­cence, during which the pa­tient made her great­est strug­gle towards a real­isa­tion of her own self through auto­nom­ous action but found that her ef­forts were con­tinu­ally de­feated by {{qq|the com­plete ab­sence of any­one in her world who could or would see some sense in her point of view}}. The trans­fer from {{qq|bad}} to {{qq|mad}} came as some­thing of a relief to the rest of the family, who {{qq|blamed them­selves for not real­ising sooner}}. As the mother said: {{qq|I knew she really could not have meant the awful things she said to me. In a way, I blame myself but, in a way, I{{m}} glad that it was an ill­ness after all, but if only I had not waited so long before I took her to a doctor.}} | ||
− | {{tab}}In ''San­ity, Mad­ness and the Family'' (the first volume of an un­com­pleted study) Drs. Laing and Esterson present ex­tracts from inter­views with mem­bers of 11 fam­il­ies, all of which con­tained daugh­ters dia­gnosed as {{qq|schizo­phrenic}}. In the Intro­duc­tion to this book the authors write: {{qq| | + | {{tab}}In ''San­ity, Mad­ness and the Family'' (the first volume of an un­com­pleted study) Drs. Laing and Esterson present ex­tracts from inter­views with mem­bers of 11 fam­il­ies, all of which con­tained daugh­ters dia­gnosed as {{qq|schizo­phrenic}}. In the Intro­duc­tion to this book the authors write: {{qq|{{e|l}}we believe that we show that the ex­peri­ence and beha­viour of schizo­phrenics is much more so­cially intel­li­gible than has come to be sup­posed by most psy­chi­atrists {{e}} we believe that the shift of point of view that these de­scrip­tions both em­body and de­mand has an histor­ical sig­ni­fic­ance no less rad­ical than the shift from a demon­o­log­ical to a clin­ical view­point 300 years ago.}} Beha­viour which is eventu­ally inter­preted by the family as a sign of mad­ness is, they argue, the out­ward ex­pres­sion of a desper­ate at­tempt on the part of the {{qq|mad one}} to {{qq|make sense of a sense­less situ­ation}}—to pre­serve some au­then­tic ele­ments of per­son­ality—a strug­gle for auto­nomy, spon­tan­eity, re­spons­ibil­ity and {{qq|free­dom}}. Here is an ex­cerpt from Laing and Esterson{{s}} tran­script of Mr. and Mrs. Gold{{s}} ac­count of their daughter: {{p|365}}{{qq|When she is her {{q|real}} self, that is, when she is {{q|well}}, she is not to be seri­ously inter­ested in writers or art, not to wear col­oured stock­ings, not to listen to jazz in a jazz club, not to bring friends home, not to stay out late. It is only from time to time that Ruth tries to as­sert her­self over against this par­ental eternal es­sence, and when she does she wears clothes to her liking, and in­sists vehem­ently on going where and with whom she wishes. Then her mother {{q|knows}} an {{q|at­tack}} is coming on. She is told she is being dif­fi­cult, in­con­sider­ate, dis­re­spect­ful, thought­less, because she is causing her parents such anxi­ety—but they do not blame or hold her re­spons­ible for all this, because they know she is odd and ill. Thus mys­ti­fied and put in an in­toler­able posi­tion she becomes ex­cited and desper­ate, makes {{q|wild}} ac­cus­a­tions that her parents do not want her to live, and runs out of the house.{{e|r}}}}<ref>{{popup|op. cit.|opere citato: cited above}}, p. 155.</ref> |
{{tab}}These writers claim, and I think demon­strate, that armed with a know­ledge of the pa­tient{{s}} ex­ist­en­tial situ­ation, it is pos­sible to make sense of what {{qq|psy­chi­atrists still by and large re­gard as non­sense}}. For example, Julie, the pa­tient in {{qq|The Ghost of the Weed Garden}}, re­ferred to her­self whilst in her {{qq|psy­chotic}} state as {{qq|Mrs. Taylor}} and as a {{qq|tolled bell}}. Dr. Laing inter­prets her chosen title {{qq|Mrs. Taylor}} as ex­pres­sing the feel­ings: {{qq|I{{m}} tailor made; I{{m}} a tailored maid; I was made, fed, clothed and tailored}} and a {{qq|tolled bell}} is also {{qq|the told belle}} {{qq|the girl who always did what she was told}}. The schizo­phrenic{{s}} {{qq|delu­sions}} of per­secu­tion are real ex­pres­sions of re­ac­tion in re­sponse to real per­secu­tion and are ex­ist­en­tially true; that is to say they are {{qq|liter­ally true state­ments within the terms of refer­ence of the indi­vidual who makes them}}.{{ref|dagger2|††}} | {{tab}}These writers claim, and I think demon­strate, that armed with a know­ledge of the pa­tient{{s}} ex­ist­en­tial situ­ation, it is pos­sible to make sense of what {{qq|psy­chi­atrists still by and large re­gard as non­sense}}. For example, Julie, the pa­tient in {{qq|The Ghost of the Weed Garden}}, re­ferred to her­self whilst in her {{qq|psy­chotic}} state as {{qq|Mrs. Taylor}} and as a {{qq|tolled bell}}. Dr. Laing inter­prets her chosen title {{qq|Mrs. Taylor}} as ex­pres­sing the feel­ings: {{qq|I{{m}} tailor made; I{{m}} a tailored maid; I was made, fed, clothed and tailored}} and a {{qq|tolled bell}} is also {{qq|the told belle}} {{qq|the girl who always did what she was told}}. The schizo­phrenic{{s}} {{qq|delu­sions}} of per­secu­tion are real ex­pres­sions of re­ac­tion in re­sponse to real per­secu­tion and are ex­ist­en­tially true; that is to say they are {{qq|liter­ally true state­ments within the terms of refer­ence of the indi­vidual who makes them}}.{{ref|dagger2|††}} | ||
− | {{tab}}The person is now launched on a {{qq|career}} as a mental pa­tient. He is con­firmed in this role by so­ciety{{s}} agents the psy­chi­atrists, in col­lu­sion with the pa­tient{{s}} family, and by pro­cess of be­trayal and de­grada­tion<ref>{{w|Erving Goffman|Erving_Goffman}} in {{w|''Asylums''|Asylums_(book)|Asylums (book)}} makes use of the term {{qq|career}} to de­note {{qq|the so­cial strand}} of a per­son{{s}} life in­au­gur­ated at the moment of his defin­i­tion as a mental pa­tient; {{qq|be­trayal fun­nel}} to de­scribe the cir­cuit of figures (relat­ives, psy­chi­atrists, etc.) whose inter­ac­tions end with the pa­tient{{s}} con­fine­ment in the {{p|374}}asylum, and {{qq|de­grada­tion ce­re­mo­nial}} for the psy­chi­atric exam­ina­tion pre­ced­ing the pa­tient{{s}} ad­mis­sion.</ref> becomes an in­mate of a mental hos­pital, which in­sti­tu­tion em­bodies {{qq|a so­cial struc­ture which in many re­spects re­du­plic­ates the mad­den­ing pecu­li­ar­ities of the pa­tient{{s}} family | + | {{tab}}The person is now launched on a {{qq|career}} as a mental pa­tient. He is con­firmed in this role by so­ciety{{s}} agents the psy­chi­atrists, in col­lu­sion with the pa­tient{{s}} family, and by pro­cess of be­trayal and de­grada­tion<ref>{{w|Erving Goffman|Erving_Goffman}} in {{w|''Asylums''|Asylums_(book)|Asylums (book)}} makes use of the term {{qq|career}} to de­note {{qq|the so­cial strand}} of a per­son{{s}} life in­au­gur­ated at the moment of his defin­i­tion as a mental pa­tient; {{qq|be­trayal fun­nel}} to de­scribe the cir­cuit of figures (relat­ives, psy­chi­atrists, etc.) whose inter­ac­tions end with the pa­tient{{s}} con­fine­ment in the {{p|374}}asylum, and {{qq|de­grada­tion ce­re­mo­nial}} for the psy­chi­atric exam­ina­tion pre­ced­ing the pa­tient{{s}} ad­mis­sion.</ref> becomes an in­mate of a mental hos­pital, which in­sti­tu­tion em­bodies {{qq|a so­cial struc­ture which in many re­spects re­du­plic­ates the mad­den­ing pecu­li­ar­ities of the pa­tient{{s}} family {{e}} he finds psy­chi­atrists, ad­min­is­trat­ors, nurses who are his verit­able par­ents, broth­ers and sisters, who play an inter­per­sonal game which only too often re­sembles in the in­tric­a­cies of its rules the game he failed in at home.}}<ref>{{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}}, {{qq|Viol­ence in Psy­chi­atry}}, {{popup|op. cit.|opere citato: cited above}}</ref> |
− | {{tab}}The ex­ist­en­tial ana­lysts have as­serted that a great deal of what passes for treat­ment in mental in­sti­tu­tions is viol­ence. Per­haps we can now begin to see what is meant by this. David Cooper in his art­icle in ''Views,'' No. 8 quotes Sartre{{s}} defin­i­tion of viol­ence: {{qq|The cor­ros­ive {{p|366}} action of the free­dom of a person on the free­dom of an­other.}} And he ex­plains this: {{qq|The action of a person | + | {{tab}}The ex­ist­en­tial ana­lysts have as­serted that a great deal of what passes for treat­ment in mental in­sti­tu­tions is viol­ence. Per­haps we can now begin to see what is meant by this. David Cooper in his art­icle in ''Views,'' No. 8 quotes Sartre{{s}} defin­i­tion of viol­ence: {{qq|The cor­ros­ive {{p|366}} action of the free­dom of a person on the free­dom of an­other.}} And he ex­plains this: {{qq|The action of a person {{e}} can de­stroy the free­dom of an­other or at least para­lyse it by mys­ti­fica­tion.}} In an art­icle printed in ''{{w|Peace News|Peace_News}}'' (22.1.65) called {{qq|Mas­sacre of the In­no­cents}} R. D. Laing makes his under­stand­ing of the word clear: {{qq|Love and viol­ence, pro­perly speak­ing, are polar op­pos­ites. Love lets the other be, but with af­fec­tion and con­cern. Viol­ence at­tempts to con­strain the other{{s}} free­dom, to force him to act in the way we desire, but with ultim­ate lack of con­cern, with in­dif­fer­ence to the other{{s}} own ex­ist­ence or des­tiny.}} The basic theme of his art­icle is that a most brutal and de­struct­ive form of viol­ence is {{qq|viol­ence mas­quer­ad­ing as love}}. In rela­tion to the family and its {{qq|schizo­phrenic}} mem­ber, action to secure care and at­ten­tion in hos­pital for some­one who is {{qq|ill}} could well be inter­preted as an ex­pres­sion of con­cern and love. Whether or not one believes that this pro­cess and the pa­tient{{s}} sub­sequent treat­ment is a form of viol­ence will de­pend in part, on whether one believes that there is any ill­ness {{qq|in}} the person to be {{qq|cured}}. It is not viol­ence to am­pu­tate a {{w|gan­gren­ous|Gangrene|Gangrene}} leg. We would all agree that it would be a viol­ent pro­ject to per­suade a person that his leg was dis­eased ({{qq|because you do not keep in step with us{{e|r}}}}), to find a sur­geon who believes that there is a so­cial need for one{{-}}legged people—and for him to cut off the leg. In the actual case of the hos­pital­ised schizo­phrenic each person in the chain sees himself as acting in the best inter­ests of the others {{e}} {{qq|but we have also to re­mem­ber that good in­ten­tions and all the wrap­pings of re­spect­abil­ity very often cover a truly cruel human real­ity.}}<ref>ibid.</ref> |
Line 146: | Line 146: | ||
{{tab}}The motiv­at­ing fantasy or belief behind the pro­vi­sion of work and {{qq|oc­cu­pa­tional ther­apy}} activ­ities is fre­quently that this in some way pro­tects the pa­tients from the erod­ing ef­fects of in­sti­tu­tion­al­isa­tion. But Dr. Cooper ob­serves: {{qq|The bitter truth is that if they sub­mis­sively {{p|368}}carry out all these re­quired tasks they become what is im­plied by these labels anyhow.}} If one wishes to en­counter the ul­ti­mate in with­drawn chronic in­sti­tu­tion­al­isa­tion one has only to visit one of the more {{qq|active}} and pro­duct­ive {{qq|factor­ies in a hos­pital}} or {{qq|indus­trial oc­cu­pa­tional ther­apy de­part­ments}}. In the unit, dis­cus­sion centred on this theme; the pa­tients were in any case show­ing re­sist­ance to con­ven­tional pro­jects. Jobs of a vigor­ous, de­struct­ive kind ({{qq|knock­ing down an {{w|air{{-}}raid shelter|Air_raid_shelter|Air raid shelter}}}}) which within a cer­tain mytho­logy, would have been sup­posed to pro­vide a proper out­let for ag­gres­sion, were not tackled with en­thu­si­asm. {{qq|People had real reasons to be angry with real other people at home and in hos­pital.}} Ham­mer­ing away at brick walls was of no rel­ev­ance. Partly as a result of fail­ure to hold the pa­tient{{s}} inter­est in tasks such as these—des­pite an at­tempt to in­flu­ence them by reduc­tion of their money al­low­ance—a situ­ation was reached in which {{qq|no organ­ised work pro­ject was pre­sented to the com­mun­ity}}. The oc­cu­pa­tional ther­ap­ist de­cided that she would be better em­ployed in the unit as an assist­ant nurse. It was at this stage of de­velop­ments that the staff became con­scious of the break­down of role bound­ar­ies: {{qq|There was a pro­gres­sive blur­ring of role between nurses, doctor, oc­cu­pa­tional ther­ap­ist and pa­tients which brought into focus a number of dis­turb­ing and ap­par­ently para­dox­ical ques­tions: for ex­ample, can pa­tients {{q|treat}} other pa­tients and can they even treat staff? Can staff real­ise quite frankly and ac­know­ledge in the com­mun­ity their own areas of in­ca­pa­city and {{q|ill­ness}} and their need for {{q|treat­ment}}? If they did what would happen next and who would con­trol it?|l}} | {{tab}}The motiv­at­ing fantasy or belief behind the pro­vi­sion of work and {{qq|oc­cu­pa­tional ther­apy}} activ­ities is fre­quently that this in some way pro­tects the pa­tients from the erod­ing ef­fects of in­sti­tu­tion­al­isa­tion. But Dr. Cooper ob­serves: {{qq|The bitter truth is that if they sub­mis­sively {{p|368}}carry out all these re­quired tasks they become what is im­plied by these labels anyhow.}} If one wishes to en­counter the ul­ti­mate in with­drawn chronic in­sti­tu­tion­al­isa­tion one has only to visit one of the more {{qq|active}} and pro­duct­ive {{qq|factor­ies in a hos­pital}} or {{qq|indus­trial oc­cu­pa­tional ther­apy de­part­ments}}. In the unit, dis­cus­sion centred on this theme; the pa­tients were in any case show­ing re­sist­ance to con­ven­tional pro­jects. Jobs of a vigor­ous, de­struct­ive kind ({{qq|knock­ing down an {{w|air{{-}}raid shelter|Air_raid_shelter|Air raid shelter}}}}) which within a cer­tain mytho­logy, would have been sup­posed to pro­vide a proper out­let for ag­gres­sion, were not tackled with en­thu­si­asm. {{qq|People had real reasons to be angry with real other people at home and in hos­pital.}} Ham­mer­ing away at brick walls was of no rel­ev­ance. Partly as a result of fail­ure to hold the pa­tient{{s}} inter­est in tasks such as these—des­pite an at­tempt to in­flu­ence them by reduc­tion of their money al­low­ance—a situ­ation was reached in which {{qq|no organ­ised work pro­ject was pre­sented to the com­mun­ity}}. The oc­cu­pa­tional ther­ap­ist de­cided that she would be better em­ployed in the unit as an assist­ant nurse. It was at this stage of de­velop­ments that the staff became con­scious of the break­down of role bound­ar­ies: {{qq|There was a pro­gres­sive blur­ring of role between nurses, doctor, oc­cu­pa­tional ther­ap­ist and pa­tients which brought into focus a number of dis­turb­ing and ap­par­ently para­dox­ical ques­tions: for ex­ample, can pa­tients {{q|treat}} other pa­tients and can they even treat staff? Can staff real­ise quite frankly and ac­know­ledge in the com­mun­ity their own areas of in­ca­pa­city and {{q|ill­ness}} and their need for {{q|treat­ment}}? If they did what would happen next and who would con­trol it?|l}} | ||
− | {{tab}}{{qq|It was at this point that the most rad­ical de­par­ture from con­ven­tional psy­chi­atric work was ini­ti­ated. If the staff re­jected pre­scribed ideas about their func­tion and if they did not quite know what to do next, why do any­thing? Why not with­draw from the whole field of hos­pital staff and pa­tient ex­pect­ation in terms of organ­ising pa­tients into activ­ity, super­vis­ing the ward do­mestic work and gen­erally {{q|treat­ing pa­tients}}.}} After this, the staff re­tained con­trol of the issu­ing of drugs and con­tinued their ad­min­is­trat­ive work. Other sec­tions of the hos­pital were made aware of the policy change in the unit and the de­tails of the new ap­proach were clari­fied at the com­mun­ity meet­ings. The im­me­di­ate ef­fect of the change was re­flected in piles of washing{{-}}up left un­done and a marked in­crease in dirt. The normal level of staff anxi­ety in­creased as the pa­tients gave no sign of organ­ising among them­selves. The pa­tients were di­vided between those who wanted a re­turn to the pre­vi­ous system and others who {{qq|ap­pre­ci­ated the more au­thentic ele­ments in the policy change}}. The crisis point came during Dr. Cooper{{s}} ab­sence on holi­day. Up to that time, many of the staff had found as­sur­ance in the belief that the evid­ent dis­order was a con­sequence of en­act­ing the Doctor{{s}} {{qq|ultra{{-}}per­mis­sive}} policy—they had done his bid­ding and what hap­pened was ul­ti­mately his re­spons­ib­il­ity. But during the period of his ab­sence, they acted together to put a limit to their in­tense anxi­ety and re­intro­duced some con­trols within the ward. This, Dr. Cooper sug­gests, was an ad­vance on their part in that they achieved a joint deci­sion and all mem­bers of the unit began to {{p|369}}ex­peri­ence the real de­mands made by the {{qq|group real­ity}}. Dr. Cooper{{s}} ob­serva­tions at this point are inter­est­ing and re­call the dis­tinc­tions made by other writers between forms of au­thor­ity—{{qq|func­tional or ar­bit­rary}} ([[Author:Martin Buber|Martin Buber]]) {{qq|overt or an­onym­ous}} ({{w|Erich Fromm|Erich_Fromm}}). Dr. Cooper writes: {{qq|This leads us on to the central prob­lem of the psy­chi­atric hos­pital of dis­tin­guish­ing between au­thentic and in­au­thentic au­thor­ity. | + | {{tab}}{{qq|It was at this point that the most rad­ical de­par­ture from con­ven­tional psy­chi­atric work was ini­ti­ated. If the staff re­jected pre­scribed ideas about their func­tion and if they did not quite know what to do next, why do any­thing? Why not with­draw from the whole field of hos­pital staff and pa­tient ex­pect­ation in terms of organ­ising pa­tients into activ­ity, super­vis­ing the ward do­mestic work and gen­erally {{q|treat­ing pa­tients}}.}} After this, the staff re­tained con­trol of the issu­ing of drugs and con­tinued their ad­min­is­trat­ive work. Other sec­tions of the hos­pital were made aware of the policy change in the unit and the de­tails of the new ap­proach were clari­fied at the com­mun­ity meet­ings. The im­me­di­ate ef­fect of the change was re­flected in piles of washing{{-}}up left un­done and a marked in­crease in dirt. The normal level of staff anxi­ety in­creased as the pa­tients gave no sign of organ­ising among them­selves. The pa­tients were di­vided between those who wanted a re­turn to the pre­vi­ous system and others who {{qq|ap­pre­ci­ated the more au­thentic ele­ments in the policy change}}. The crisis point came during Dr. Cooper{{s}} ab­sence on holi­day. Up to that time, many of the staff had found as­sur­ance in the belief that the evid­ent dis­order was a con­sequence of en­act­ing the Doctor{{s}} {{qq|ultra{{-}}per­mis­sive}} policy—they had done his bid­ding and what hap­pened was ul­ti­mately his re­spons­ib­il­ity. But during the period of his ab­sence, they acted together to put a limit to their in­tense anxi­ety and re­intro­duced some con­trols within the ward. This, Dr. Cooper sug­gests, was an ad­vance on their part in that they achieved a joint deci­sion and all mem­bers of the unit began to {{p|369}}ex­peri­ence the real de­mands made by the {{qq|group real­ity}}. Dr. Cooper{{s}} ob­serva­tions at this point are inter­est­ing and re­call the dis­tinc­tions made by other writers between forms of au­thor­ity—{{qq|func­tional or ar­bit­rary}} ([[Author:Martin Buber|Martin Buber]]) {{qq|overt or an­onym­ous}} ({{w|Erich Fromm|Erich_Fromm}}). Dr. Cooper writes: {{qq|This leads us on to the central prob­lem of the psy­chi­atric hos­pital of dis­tin­guish­ing between au­thentic and in­au­thentic au­thor­ity. {{e}} The au­thor­ity of the au­thor­ity person is granted him by ar­bit­rary so­cial defin­ition rather than on the basis of any real ex­pert­ise he may pos­sess. If staff have the cour­age to shift them­selves from this false posi­tion they may dis­cover real sources of au­thor­ity in them­selves. They may also dis­cover such sources of au­thor­ity in {{q|the others}} who are de­fined as their pa­tients. {{e}} Per­haps the most central char­ac­ter­istic of au­thentic leader­ship is the re­lin­quish­ing of the im­pulse to domin­ate others. Domin­ation here means con­trol­ling the beha­viour of others where their beha­viour repre­sents for the leader pro­jected as­pects of his own ex­peri­ence. By domin­ation of the other the leader pro­duces for him­self the illu­sion that his own in­ternal organ­isa­tion is more and more per­fectly ordered. The {{w|Nazi|Nazi_Germany|Nazi Germany}} {{w|ex­term­in­ation camps|Extermination_camp|Extermination camp}} were one pro­duct of this Dream of Per­fec­tion. The mental hos­pital, along with other in­sti­tu­tions in our so­ciety, is an­other.}} Sub­sti­tute {{qq|school}} for {{qq|psy­chi­atric hos­pital}} and {{qq|pupil}} for {{qq|pa­tient}} and one sees the wider rel­ev­ance of this pas­sage. |
{{tab}}The work­ers in the unit were faced with con­flict­ing pres­sures—pres­sures to con­form with the cus­tom­ary ap­proaches facing them in so­cial systems and rela­tion­ships out­side the unit (pro­fes­sional ad­vance­ment and will­ing­ness to con­form to some ex­tent going together)—and con­trary pres­sure from within the unit itself. This again re­sulted in ten­sion which obliged them to face the need for {{qq|com­mit­ment one way or the other}}. | {{tab}}The work­ers in the unit were faced with con­flict­ing pres­sures—pres­sures to con­form with the cus­tom­ary ap­proaches facing them in so­cial systems and rela­tion­ships out­side the unit (pro­fes­sional ad­vance­ment and will­ing­ness to con­form to some ex­tent going together)—and con­trary pres­sure from within the unit itself. This again re­sulted in ten­sion which obliged them to face the need for {{qq|com­mit­ment one way or the other}}. | ||
Line 154: | Line 154: | ||
{{tab}}An as­sess­ment of the suc­cess of the {{qq|anti{{-}}hos­pital}} in terms of {{qq|results}} (usu­ally meas­ured in such cases by the in­cid­ence of re{{-}}ad­mis­sion) would not be any more mean­ing­ful than a judge­ment on Summer­hill based simply on the pupil{{s}} suc­cess rate in public exam­ina­tions. The cri­terion of re{{-}}ad­mis­sion rates is also in­ad­equate in that staff en­cour­aged pa­tients to return after dis­charge if they felt that a return to the unit would be of value to them. Never­the­less, even by this stand­ard the {{qq|anti{{-}}hos­pital}} re­sults com­pare fa­vour­ably with those achieved by more widely ac­cepted methods—17 per cent of pa­tients being re{{-}}ad­mitted during a one{{-}}year period fol­low­ing dis­charge. In the issue of the ''{{w|British Med­ical Journal|The_BMJ|The BMJ}}'' which in­cluded these re­sults Dr. Cooper stated his belief that the ex­peri­ment has estab­lished {{qq|at least {{p|370}}a ''prima facie'' case for rad­ical re­vision of the thera­peutic strat­egy em­ployed in most units for schizo­phrenia}}.<ref>''{{w|British Med­ical Journal|The_BMJ|The BMJ}}'', No. 5476, p. 1462.</ref> | {{tab}}An as­sess­ment of the suc­cess of the {{qq|anti{{-}}hos­pital}} in terms of {{qq|results}} (usu­ally meas­ured in such cases by the in­cid­ence of re{{-}}ad­mis­sion) would not be any more mean­ing­ful than a judge­ment on Summer­hill based simply on the pupil{{s}} suc­cess rate in public exam­ina­tions. The cri­terion of re{{-}}ad­mis­sion rates is also in­ad­equate in that staff en­cour­aged pa­tients to return after dis­charge if they felt that a return to the unit would be of value to them. Never­the­less, even by this stand­ard the {{qq|anti{{-}}hos­pital}} re­sults com­pare fa­vour­ably with those achieved by more widely ac­cepted methods—17 per cent of pa­tients being re{{-}}ad­mitted during a one{{-}}year period fol­low­ing dis­charge. In the issue of the ''{{w|British Med­ical Journal|The_BMJ|The BMJ}}'' which in­cluded these re­sults Dr. Cooper stated his belief that the ex­peri­ment has estab­lished {{qq|at least {{p|370}}a ''prima facie'' case for rad­ical re­vision of the thera­peutic strat­egy em­ployed in most units for schizo­phrenia}}.<ref>''{{w|British Med­ical Journal|The_BMJ|The BMJ}}'', No. 5476, p. 1462.</ref> | ||
− | {{tab}}As a post­script to the fore­go­ing, I can deal only sketch­ily with an in­triguing aspect of the work of the British ex­ist­en­tial­ists—their ideas on the nature of {{qq|madness}} itself. A re­cur­rent theme in R. D. Laing{{s}} writ­ing is his em­phasis on the dis­astrously narrow field of ex­peri­ence which is cred­ited in con­tempor­ary life, as {{qq|real­ity}}. {{qq|We are far more out of touch with even the near­est ap­proaches of the in­fin­ite reaches of inner space, than we now are with the reaches of outer space. | + | {{tab}}As a post­script to the fore­go­ing, I can deal only sketch­ily with an in­triguing aspect of the work of the British ex­ist­en­tial­ists—their ideas on the nature of {{qq|madness}} itself. A re­cur­rent theme in R. D. Laing{{s}} writ­ing is his em­phasis on the dis­astrously narrow field of ex­peri­ence which is cred­ited in con­tempor­ary life, as {{qq|real­ity}}. {{qq|We are far more out of touch with even the near­est ap­proaches of the in­fin­ite reaches of inner space, than we now are with the reaches of outer space. {{e}} We are so out of touch with this realm that many people can now argue seri­ously that it does not exist.}}<ref>{{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}}, {{qq|What is Schizo­phrenia?}}, {{popup|op. cit.|opere citato: cited above}}</ref> It is no sur­prise that Dr. Laing has spoken on the power of the drug {{w|LSD|Lysergic_acid_diethylamide}} to ex­tend the bound­aries of real­ity for those who make use of it re­spons­ibly. In ''The Divided Self'' he cites the value of the {{w|Proph­etic Books|William_Blake's_prophetic_books|William Blake's prophetic books}} of {{w|William Blake|William_Blake}} and (in ''The Self and Others'') re­lates Blake to his pre­vi­ous de­scrip­tion of a {{qq|psy­chotic}}: {{qq|Blake{{s}} posi­tion seems to me to have been this. Single {{q|vision}} (one mod­al­ity of ex­peri­ence) is death. This is what most people regard as san­ity.}} He also charts in this book and in other art­icles, the dual­ism im­plicit in the idea of fantasy to be found in most psycho{{-}}ana­lytic works and in the minds of a good many psy­chi­atrists: {{qq|A very con­fused dual­istic philo­sophy of psy­chical and phys­ical, inner and outer, mental and phys­ical.}} It is the opin­ion of Laing and Cooper that what is clin­ic­ally de­scribed as {{qq|a schizo­phrenic break­down}} may be the onset in the indi­vidual of a voyage into the world of inner space and time. The word {{qq|inner}} is mis­lead­ing, sug­gest­ing a place loc­ated {{qq|inside}} the person; as they use the word it refers to {{qq|our own per­sonal idiom of ex­peri­encing our bodies, other people, the anim­ate and in­anim­ate world: imagin­ation, dreams, fantasy{{e|r}}}}. And far from being a {{qq|dis­ease}} this pro­cess, or {{qq|voyage}}, may well be the path to greater aware­ness, the crisis of the indi­vidual{{s}} strug­gle to real­ise him­self as a person, even—the onset of san­ity! (Dr. Cooper has sug­gested that it may be {{qq|when people start to become sane that they enter the mental hos­pital}}). A person under­go­ing this ex­peri­ence may well be {{qq|dif­fi­cult for others}} and is in need of special care—but not {{qq|treat­ment}} in {{qq|the quite bizar­rely in­con­gru­ous con­text of the mental hos­pital}}. Those who care for him should as­sume the role of guides—and people cap­able of pro­vid­ing this help will very prob­ably be those who have them­selves been through similar ex­peri­ences: {{qq|We need a place where people who have trav­elled further and, con­sequently, may be more lost than psy­chi­atrists and other sane people, can find their way ''further'' into inner space and time, and back again {{e}} the person will be guided with full so­cial en­cour­age­ment and sanc­tion into inner space and time, by people who have been there and back again. Psy­chi­atric­ally, this would appear as ex{{-}}pa­tients help­ing future pa­tients go mad.}}<ref>ibid.</ref> |
{{tab}}No fully auto­nomous unit in which this pro­cess can take place exists at the present moment,{{ref|3dagger|†††}} but we can de­duce from the {{qq|anti{{-}}{{p|371}}hos­pital}} ex­peri­ment, a good deal about what is re­quired for its suc­cess­ful<!-- 'sucessful' in original --> real­isa­tion. | {{tab}}No fully auto­nomous unit in which this pro­cess can take place exists at the present moment,{{ref|3dagger|†††}} but we can de­duce from the {{qq|anti{{-}}{{p|371}}hos­pital}} ex­peri­ment, a good deal about what is re­quired for its suc­cess­ful<!-- 'sucessful' in original --> real­isa­tion. | ||
Line 162: | Line 162: | ||
− | {{tab}}The only ex­tended criti­cism known to me of the work and ideas of these British psy­chi­atrists is an article by B. A. Farrell called {{qq|The Logic of Ex­ist­en­tial Ana­lysis}} which ap­peared in ''New Society'' ({{popup|1.10.65|1 October 1965}}). This writer argues that the ex­ist­en­tial­ists have dis­missed ortho­dox views on the causes and treat­ment of schizo­phrenia on in­ad­equate grounds and also make logic­ally un­warrant­able de­duc­tions from their re­search into the fam­il­ies of schizo­phrenics. Re­fer­ring to the claim of Laing and Esterson that they have made the {{qq|symp­toms}} of schizo­phrenia in­tel­li­gible, he makes the point that even if they are suc­cess­ful in doing this, making the symp­toms in­tel­li­gible is not the same thing as estab­lish­ing truth for their hypo­thesis. Farrell com­ments that {{qq|this would be a trivial point to make}} if we had other grounds for believ­ing that the nar­rat­ives were true. In rela­tion to their sug­ges­tions for treat­ment he asks for evid­ence that units of the {{qq|anti{{-}}hos­pital}} type pro­duce results {{qq|as good as, or better than, the tradi­tional methods}}. In con­clu­sion he ad­vises them that some of the op­posi­tion to their work might not have been so vehe­ment had they avoided {{qq|abus­ive}} and {{qq|in­tem­per­ate}} lan­guage in their refer­ences to the Estab­lish­ment; and also that {{qq|they would help them­selves if they could avoid giving the im­pres­sion that they had fallen in love with their schizo­phrenic pa­tients. | + | {{tab}}The only ex­tended criti­cism known to me of the work and ideas of these British psy­chi­atrists is an article by B. A. Farrell called {{qq|The Logic of Ex­ist­en­tial Ana­lysis}} which ap­peared in ''New Society'' ({{popup|1.10.65|1 October 1965}}). This writer argues that the ex­ist­en­tial­ists have dis­missed ortho­dox views on the causes and treat­ment of schizo­phrenia on in­ad­equate grounds and also make logic­ally un­warrant­able de­duc­tions from their re­search into the fam­il­ies of schizo­phrenics. Re­fer­ring to the claim of Laing and Esterson that they have made the {{qq|symp­toms}} of schizo­phrenia in­tel­li­gible, he makes the point that even if they are suc­cess­ful in doing this, making the symp­toms in­tel­li­gible is not the same thing as estab­lish­ing truth for their hypo­thesis. Farrell com­ments that {{qq|this would be a trivial point to make}} if we had other grounds for believ­ing that the nar­rat­ives were true. In rela­tion to their sug­ges­tions for treat­ment he asks for evid­ence that units of the {{qq|anti{{-}}hos­pital}} type pro­duce results {{qq|as good as, or better than, the tradi­tional methods}}. In con­clu­sion he ad­vises them that some of the op­posi­tion to their work might not have been so vehe­ment had they avoided {{qq|abus­ive}} and {{qq|in­tem­per­ate}} lan­guage in their refer­ences to the Estab­lish­ment; and also that {{qq|they would help them­selves if they could avoid giving the im­pres­sion that they had fallen in love with their schizo­phrenic pa­tients. {{e|r}}}} |
− | {{tab}}Cor­re­spond­ents in sub­sequent issues sug­gested some answers to these criti­cisms. Com­ment­ing on Mr. Farrell{{s}} re­mark on the lack of sup­port­ive evid­ence, Dr. John Bowlby wrote: {{qq|Although Dr. Laing{{s}} is the only psy­chi­atric group in this country pub­lish­ing ma­terial of its sort, in the {{w|United States|United_States}} there are several. The two best known are the group at the {{w|Na­tional In­sti­tute of Mental Health|National_Institute_of_Mental_Health}} | + | {{tab}}Cor­re­spond­ents in sub­sequent issues sug­gested some answers to these criti­cisms. Com­ment­ing on Mr. Farrell{{s}} re­mark on the lack of sup­port­ive evid­ence, Dr. John Bowlby wrote: {{qq|Although Dr. Laing{{s}} is the only psy­chi­atric group in this country pub­lish­ing ma­terial of its sort, in the {{w|United States|United_States}} there are several. The two best known are the group at the {{w|Na­tional In­sti­tute of Mental Health|National_Institute_of_Mental_Health}} {{e}} and the one at {{w|Palo Alto|Palo_Alto,_California}}. {{e}} Each of these re­search groups has used methods and re­ported find­ings es­sen­tially similar to those of Dr. Laing. Some of their most re­cent re­ports {{e}} are of pro­jects that at cri­tical points in the pro­ced­ure are {{q|blind}} in just the way that Mr. Farrell rightly re­quests. In addi­tion a number of find­ings de­rived from quite other methods are sup­port­ive. {{e}} There is thus sub­stan­tial evid­ence de­rived from more than one method in sup­port of the Laing type of hypo­thesis. {{e}} When com­pared with evid­ence ad­vanced to sup­port other types of hypo­thesis, it is not un­im­pres­sive. On the one hand it is ''far more sub­stan­tial'' than any yet of­fered in sup­port of psycho{{-}}ana­lytic theor­ies, whether tradi­tional or {{w|Kleinian|Melanie_Klein|Melanie Klein}}, and, on the other, more con­sist­ent than that sup­port­ing a genetic{{-}}bio­chem­ical type of theory}} (my italics).<ref>Ex­tract from letter in ''{{w|New So­ciety|New_Society}}'', 4th November, 1965.</ref> |
{{tab}}I have already made some re­fer­ence to the {{qq|re­sults}}, in terms of re{{-}}ad­mis­sions, of the {{qq|anti{{-}}hos­pital}} which were pub­lished in the {{p|372}}''{{w|BMA Journal|The_BMJ|The BMJ}}'' and re­printed in ''New So­ciety'' three months after the ap­pear­ance of Mr. Farrell{{s}} art­icle. They are indeed as good as, or better than, re­sults achieved by tradi­tional methods. | {{tab}}I have already made some re­fer­ence to the {{qq|re­sults}}, in terms of re{{-}}ad­mis­sions, of the {{qq|anti{{-}}hos­pital}} which were pub­lished in the {{p|372}}''{{w|BMA Journal|The_BMJ|The BMJ}}'' and re­printed in ''New So­ciety'' three months after the ap­pear­ance of Mr. Farrell{{s}} art­icle. They are indeed as good as, or better than, re­sults achieved by tradi­tional methods. | ||
Line 172: | Line 172: | ||
{{tab}}As I hope I have suc­ceeded in in­dic­ating in this art­icle, the work of Drs. Laing, Cooper and Esterson con­sti­tutes far more than just an­other theory of what causes {{qq|schizo­phrenia}}; a cor­re­spond­ent in ''New So­ciety'' char­ac­ter­ised it as {{qq|an ex­plor­a­tion of the neces­sary condi­tions for a fully human rela­tion­ship}}.<ref>A phrase from a letter by J. D. Ingleby ({{w|Ap­plied Psy­cho­logy Re­search Unit|Cognition_and_Brain_Sciences_Unit|Cognition and Brain Sciences Unit}}, {{w|Cambridge}}), ''{{w|New So­ciety|New_Society}}'', 28th October, 1965.</ref> | {{tab}}As I hope I have suc­ceeded in in­dic­ating in this art­icle, the work of Drs. Laing, Cooper and Esterson con­sti­tutes far more than just an­other theory of what causes {{qq|schizo­phrenia}}; a cor­re­spond­ent in ''New So­ciety'' char­ac­ter­ised it as {{qq|an ex­plor­a­tion of the neces­sary condi­tions for a fully human rela­tion­ship}}.<ref>A phrase from a letter by J. D. Ingleby ({{w|Ap­plied Psy­cho­logy Re­search Unit|Cognition_and_Brain_Sciences_Unit|Cognition and Brain Sciences Unit}}, {{w|Cambridge}}), ''{{w|New So­ciety|New_Society}}'', 28th October, 1965.</ref> | ||
− | {{tab}}Dr. Laing has sug­gested that the reason why ex­plor­ation of the {{qq|inner}} world of the self is in­valid­ated by so­ciety as {{qq|mad­ness}} is that such ex­peri­ence is sub­vers­ive. {{qq|And it is sub­vers­ive because it is ''real.''}}<ref>{{qq|A Ten Day Voyage}}, ''{{l|Views|https://lccn.loc.gov/sf83002178|Library of Congress catalogue entry}}'', No. 8.</ref> Dei­fied de­struct­ive illu­sions—{{qq|the health of {{w|ster­ling|Pound_sterling|Pound sterling}}}}, {{qq|the {{w|Red menace|Red_Scare|Red Scare}}}}, {{qq|the inter­ests of the State}}—are the stage{{-}}props of normal so­cial life and these phantoms are con­firmed as {{qq|real­ity}} by all the re­sources avail­able. Because the vast ma­jor­ity of people act in terms of these nega­tions {{qq|we find our­selves threat­ened by ex­term­in­a­tion that will be re­cip­rocal, that no one wishes, that every­one fears, that may just hap­pen to us {{q|because}} no one knows how to stop it. | + | {{tab}}Dr. Laing has sug­gested that the reason why ex­plor­ation of the {{qq|inner}} world of the self is in­valid­ated by so­ciety as {{qq|mad­ness}} is that such ex­peri­ence is sub­vers­ive. {{qq|And it is sub­vers­ive because it is ''real.''}}<ref>{{qq|A Ten Day Voyage}}, ''{{l|Views|https://lccn.loc.gov/sf83002178|Library of Congress catalogue entry}}'', No. 8.</ref> Dei­fied de­struct­ive illu­sions—{{qq|the health of {{w|ster­ling|Pound_sterling|Pound sterling}}}}, {{qq|the {{w|Red menace|Red_Scare|Red Scare}}}}, {{qq|the inter­ests of the State}}—are the stage{{-}}props of normal so­cial life and these phantoms are con­firmed as {{qq|real­ity}} by all the re­sources avail­able. Because the vast ma­jor­ity of people act in terms of these nega­tions {{qq|we find our­selves threat­ened by ex­term­in­a­tion that will be re­cip­rocal, that no one wishes, that every­one fears, that may just hap­pen to us {{q|because}} no one knows how to stop it. {{e}} Every­one will by carry­ing out orders. Where do they come from? Always from else­where.{{e|r}}}}<ref>{{qq|Us and Them}}, {{popup|op. cit.|opere citato: cited above}}</ref> Dr. Cooper has also de­scribed this tragic condi­tion: {{qq|The myth of {{w|Thanatos}} is a self{{-}}actu­al­izing phant­asy. The {{w|bomb|Atomic_bombings_of_Hiroshima_and_Nagasaki|Atomic bombings of Hiroshima and Nagasaki}} really did drop on {{w|Hiroshima}}. {{e}} The basic para­dox that we live is that man­kind needs illu­sions but the illu­sions it needs de­stroy it. Even through rela­tively in­noc­u­ous or {{q|good}} illu­sions we im­prison our­selves meta­phys­ically and then find we have built real prison walls (per­haps around some­one else).}}<ref>{{qq|Freud Re­visited}}—a review of {{w|Herbert Marcuse|Herbert_Marcuse}}{{s}} ''{{w|Eros and Civil­iza­tion|Eros_and_Civilization}}'', ''{{w|New Left Review|New_Left_Review}}'', No. 20.</ref> |
− | {{tab}}I hope that, as Dr. Laing has hinted, their future work will in­volve and imply further cri­ti­cism in depth, of our so­ciety; if this is the case it will have di­rect rel­ev­ance for con­tem­por­ary anarch­ism (not­with­stand­ing the as­so­ci­a­tion of these writers with a form of {{w|Marx­ism|Marxism}}). In con­clu­sion, I would risk the state­ment that the body of work they have so far pro­duced—de­rived as it is from so­cial psy­cho­logy and ob­serva­tional re­search in the best [[Author:Alex Comfort|Alex Comfort]] manner—al­ready {{qq|up­holds}} a form of anarch­ism—a form which could be typ­i­fied by a phrase of Dr. Cooper{{s}}: {{qq|The way of auto­nomy}}. | + | {{tab}}I hope that, as Dr. Laing has hinted, their future work will in­volve and imply further cri­ti­cism in depth, of our so­ciety; if this is the case it will have di­rect rel­ev­ance for con­tem­por­ary anarch­ism (not­with­stand­ing the as­so­ci­a­tion of these writers with a form of {{w|Marx­ism|Marxism}}). In con­clu­sion, I would risk the state­ment that the body of work they have {{p|373}}so far pro­duced—de­rived as it is from so­cial psy­cho­logy and ob­serva­tional re­search in the best [[Author:Alex Comfort|Alex Comfort]] manner—al­ready {{qq|up­holds}} a form of anarch­ism—a form which could be typ­i­fied by a phrase of Dr. Cooper{{s}}: {{qq|The way of auto­nomy}}. |
----- | ----- | ||
− | <font size="2">{{hang|{{note|aster|*}} See ''The Divided Self'', pp. 41-42. For an ac­count of the con­sequences of the ob­struc­tion of this oc­cur­rence: {{qq|an ex­ist­en­tially dead child}} see p. 183. In ''{{l|Views|https://lccn.loc.gov/sf83002178|Library of Congress catalogue entry}}'', No. 8, {{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}} writes: {{qq| | + | <font size="2">{{hang|{{note|aster|*}} See ''The Divided Self'', pp. 41-42. For an ac­count of the con­sequences of the ob­struc­tion of this oc­cur­rence: {{qq|an ex­ist­en­tially dead child}} see p. 183. In ''{{l|Views|https://lccn.loc.gov/sf83002178|Library of Congress catalogue entry}}'', No. 8, {{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}} writes: {{qq|{{e|l}}the begin­ning of per­sonal de­velop­ment is never pure passiv­ity. {{e}} From the first moment of mother-child inter­action, where each is an­other to the other, the child is in the posi­tion of having to ini­ti­ate the pro­ject to become who­ever he is to be, and this is in prin­ciple a free choice, his free crea­tion of his essen­tial nature.}} |
{{note|aster2|**}}<!-- single asterisk in original --> An art­icle in ''{{w|The Observer|The_Observer}}'' ({{popup|4.9.66|4 September 1966}}) an­nounced the forma­tion of {{qq|Pro­ject 70}}—{{qq|a plan to rescue men­tally normal old people from the wards of mental hos­pitals.}} | {{note|aster2|**}}<!-- single asterisk in original --> An art­icle in ''{{w|The Observer|The_Observer}}'' ({{popup|4.9.66|4 September 1966}}) an­nounced the forma­tion of {{qq|Pro­ject 70}}—{{qq|a plan to rescue men­tally normal old people from the wards of mental hos­pitals.}} |
Latest revision as of 11:43, 11 October 2021
an introduction to
existential analysis
This article aims to draw attention to the work of a group of British psychiatrists of whom the best known are R. D. Laing and David Cooper. They have achieved some notoriety in this country because of the extent of their divergence, both in theory and practice, from current psychiatric orthodoxy—and particularly as a consequence of their references to the prevalent “treatment” of the mentally ill as “violence”. As a teacher, I am not qualified to attempt more than an outline of their ideas as understood by me, after reading their books and articles and some related studies. But the implications of the work of the British existentialist group extend beyond the limits of psychiatry—and the very generality of their assertions invites a response from the layman. Writing of the process which in their view results in the ultimate invalidation of persons through the labelling of them as “mad”, Laing asks: “. . . what function does this procedure serve for the civic order? These questions are only beginning to be asked, much less answered. . . . Socially, this work must now move to further understanding . . . of the meaning of all this within the larger context of the civic order of society—that is, of the political order, of the ways persons exercise control and power over one another.” (New Left Review, No. 28.) Anarchism is about just this, and any theory, from whatever discipline, which leads to a questioning of the political order of society should have relevance for us—and we should know something about it.
Dr. Laing has written that his main intellectual indebtedness is to “the existential tradition”—Kierkegaard, Jaspers, Heidegger, Binswanger, Tillich and Sartre—and of these there is no doubt that Sartre’s influence has been the greatest. The British analysts have clearly worked out their own theoretical basis and in many instances have developed Sartre’s ideas rather than merely adopted them as they stand. I am not certain, for example, how completely Laing and Cooper share Sartre’s total rejection of the concept of “the unconscious”. However, their book Reason and Violence: A Decade of Sartre’s Philosophy 1950-1960 (Tavistock, 1964) opens with a complimentary prefatory note from the French philosopher—I believe this is an unusual honour for a book about his ideas—and this imprimatur suggests that whatever their divergencies, they cannot be basic.
In anarchy 44 J.-P. Sartre is referred to as “one of the foremostThe first of four episodes of this essay are intended to create a setting against which existential analysis may be viewed.
EXISTENTIAL FREEDOM
“Man cannot be sometimes slave and sometimes free; he is wholly and forever free, or he is not free at all.”
Sartre argues against the Freudian three-way split of the personality into id, ego and super-ego and the psycho-analytic dictum of conscious behaviour as determined by drives, instincts and desires allegedly emanating from the id. As Sartre’s arguments hinge upon his stated belief in man’s ontological freedom, Freud’s project of “determination by the unconscious” is met with similar objections to those made against other determinist theories and I need not attempt to summarise them here.[7] The only valid form of therapy is one aimed at discovering an individual’s fundamental project-of-being—and this is the purpose of existential analysis (or psycho-analysis; the prefix seems to be optional). “The principle of this psycho-analysis is that man is a totality and not a collection; he therefore expresses himself in his totality in the most insignificant and the most superficial aspects of his conduct” (Being and Nothingness). Through the use of a technique or method based on such assumptions the initially “crazy” actions of the insane may be made comprehensible—and may even appear “reasonable” if a picture of the world in which the patient lives can be assembled.
R. D. Laing has written that “only by the most outrageous violation of ourselves have we achieved our capacity to live in relative adjustment to a civilisation apparently driven to its own destruction” and has described the “normal” person in the present age as “a half-crazed creature, more or less adjusted to a mad world”.[8] What is the norm that gives the generally accepted meaning to such relative descriptions as “mad”, “insane”, “maladjusted”? And what is the significance of what is done to the people that are disqualified when measured against this criterion; the people that the mad officials label as “officially mad”?
THE INSANE IN A MAD WORLD
“In the context of our present madness that we call normality, sanity, freedom, all our frames of reference are ambiguous and equivocal.”
By far the largest group is the third—the “neurotics and psychotics”. Among these “schizophrenia” is the most common diagnosis. “In most European countries about one per cent of the population go to hospital at least once in their lifetime with the diagnosis schizophrenia.”[10] But what meaning can be given to these statistics and assessments without a standard of sanity or madness? “Definitions of mental health propounded by the experts usually reduce to the notion of conformism, to a set of more or less arbitrarily posited social norms. . . .”[11] The labelling of people as mad can have the social function of defining the area of “sanity”—perhaps there is a parallel with Durkheim’s theory of crime and punishment as “necessary” to respectable society to mark off the limits of permissible and tolerated behaviour. “Society needs lunatics in order that it may regard itself as sane.”[12] It could also be argued that certain kinds of society “need” lunatics as their managers; a discussion in Peace News recently was concerned with the uncertifiable madness of the American President in relation to a “collective norm of insanity”. A correspondent noted: “No significant member of a power establishment can ever be ‘certifiably insane’ since it is this same establishment which determines the definitions of ‘sanity’ and ‘insanity’ and which decides—checked only by the occasional conscience of an occasional professional medical man—when ‘insanity’ becomes ‘certifiable’.”[13]
In official statistics there must, in any case, be a murky overlap area between what comes out as “crime” and what as “lunacy”—and a lot of luck in who ends up in which institution. Perhaps it is the institutional bureaucracy that has most need of the labels: “According to the commonsense definition,” writes Dr. Theodore Szasz, “mental health is the ability to play whatever the game of social living might consist of and to play it well. Conversely, to refuse to play, or to play badly, means that the person is mentally ill. The question may now be raised as to what are the differences, if any, between social nonconformity (or deviation) and mental illness. Leaving technical psychiatric considerations aside for the moment, I shall argue that the difference between these two notions—as expressed for example by the statements ‘He is wrong’ and ‘He is mentally ill’—does not lie in any observable facts to which they may point, but may consist only of a difference in our attitudes toward our subject.”[14] What sort of behaviour is likely to lead those with the appropriate attitudes to see signs of mental illness and to set going the transfer process from
CURATIVE—OR PUNITIVE?
“Many of us, for quite some time have considered that problems of punishment and repression are most acute in the context of imprisonment. But this is not so; the really intractable problem in this sphere is that of the mental hospital.”
In his account of “de-institutionalisation” (anarchy 4) Colin Ward referred to the prison as “the most sinister of institutions” and no doubt it is. But as anarchists are aware, the state can make skilful use of the “approved” concepts of crime and criminality to divert attention from its own more grandiose but identical activities: so we should be alert to the possibility that the institutions openly labelled as prisons are not the only ones serving that function. Suppose, as Roger Moody says in his article that mental hospital and prison are “different terms for the same thing”? If there is some truth in this there is consequently an additional danger in that anything called a “hospital” has automatically a protective cocoon around it as a result of its claim to provide therapy. But surely the “voluntary” presence of many of the patients in mental hospitals ensures that they cannot have a punitive character or effect? A different approach is suggested by the American sociologist Erving Goffman: “. . . We must see the mental hospital, in the recent historical context in which it developed, as one among a network of institutions designed to provide a residence for various categories of socially troublesome people.”[16]
As Malatesta noted in his essay “Anarchy”, “Organs and functions are inseparable terms. Take from an organ its function, and either the organ will die, or the function will reinstate itself.” The existence of the mental hospital is justified by its function of curing the mentally ill. “The patient’s presence in the hospital is taken as prima facie evidence that he is mentally ill, since the hospitalization of these persons is what the institution is for.” A very common answer to a patient who claims he is sane is the statement: “If you aren’t sick you wouldn’t be in the hospital.”[18] One consequence of this for the person initiated into a “career” as a mental patient is that his past life will be restructured in terms of a “case history”—and he may be denied rights of privacy over what he previously regarded as “his own business”—any facet of which may now provide evidence of “symptoms”.[19] Once inside, the patient may find the internal organisation of the asylum dominated by a “ward system” separating patients off into “disease” categories, the various levels providing different standards of accommodation, food and grounds-and-town “privileges”, among other factors of importance in the life of the patient. The material and social provisions on each ward level are officially those that are most appropriate to the mental condition of the patient. But whilst the system may be justified by its partisans on these grounds, it has an unacknowledged function as an inmate-controlling device. There is a direct parallel here with the alleged purpose of the streaming system in schools; invariably defended on the basis of its educational value yet actually operating in schools as an important component of the disciplinary system. And in asylums, as in schools, these “divide and rule” disciplinary strategies have developed as the best method of “management by a small staff of a large number of involuntary inmates”.
Because society needs lunatics to provide it with reassurance of its own sanity, so it has need of institutions to contain them. But as with prisons, the real enemy is not the material structure—“It is our own anxiety which forces us to lock people up”[20]—and it is through anxiety about our own sanity that we build walls around the “mentally ill”. “Mental hospitals are not found in our society because supervisors, psychiatrists and attendants want jobs; mental hospitals are found because there is a market for them. If all the mental hospitals in a given region were emptied and closed down today, tomorrow relatives, police, and judges would raise a clamour for new ones; and these true clients of the mental hospital would demand an institution to satisfy their needs.”[21]
SCHIZOPHRENIA—A PSEUDO-DISEASE?
“In the popular mind the schizophrenic is the proto-typical madman—author of the totally gratuitous crazy act that always has overtones of violence to others.”
One psycho-analytic view is that schizophrenia is the outcome of a split between a person’s “conscious” and “unconscious” forces which in the normal state are believed to work simultaneously. Another idea—in schizophrenia “there is a subtle change in brain chemistry which interferes in some way with nerve impulses.”[23] The popularity of this view and others similar to it has led to an emphasis on surgical or physical treatment such as electro-convulsive therapy (a low voltage shock passed between the temples) and, in some cases, operations on the brain (leucotomy and lobotomy). In at least one London hospital schizophrenics have been placed in deep freeze. Drugs are much used. And it seems that what are taken to be the symptoms of the disease can be eliminated by the use of such means at least for a time. As Sartre observed, one “can obtain a result by using merely technical methods.” But, as the writer of a survey in The Observer (5.6.66) commented: “No one knows, except in the fuzziest outline, what the treatments do. And none of them is a cure.” John Linsie in his article in anarchy 24 pointed out that the effectiveness of drugs and E.C.T. in temporarily removing “symptoms” has perhaps prevented more widespread research into the basic aetiology of the “disease”. Schizophrenia often occurs within the same family and some researchers believe that it is transmitted genetically. John Linsie quoted Mayer-Gross: “It may now be regarded as established that hereditary factors play a predominant role in the causation of schizophrenic psychosis”—and then trumped this with the opinion of another expert, Roth: “No simple genetic hypothesis accords with all the facts.”
This I hope is enough to provide some basis for R. D. Laing’s and A. Esterson’s statement in the introduction to Sanity, Madness and the Family that there is no more disputed condition in the whole field of medicine. “The one thing certain about schizophrenia is that it is a diagnosis, that is a clinical label, applied by some people to others.”[24] The essentially social process which results ultimately in the fixing of this label to one person is the underlying theme of three books and a good many articles by Dr. Laing and his colleagues. I shall try to outline their account of this process subsequently, but an idea of their truly radical conclusions can be given here:
“We do not use the term ‘schizophrenia’ to denote any identifiable condition which we believe exists ‘in’ one person.”[25]
“I do not myself believe that there is any such ‘condition’ as schizophrenia. . . .”[26]
“Schizophrenia is not a disease in one person but rather a crazy“Schizophrenia, if it means anything, is a more or less characteristic mode of disturbed group behaviour. There are no schizophrenics.”[28]
THE FAMILY—“FROM GOOD TO BAD TO MAD”
“Over the last two decades there has been a growing dissatisfaction with any theory or study of the individual which artificially isolates him from the context of his life, interpersonal and social.”
Sartre holds that all groups are structured against an awareness of a “spectator”. This “spectator” may be an individual—as in the case of children seeing themselves as “pupils” in relation to a teacher—or another group, as in the case of workers constituting themselves against managers. This spactator he calls the “Third” for whom the group exists as an object. Laing and Cooper seem to have developed their views on groups—and in particular, the family system of the future “schizophrenic”—from Sartre’s interpretation of group structure and cohesion. In elaborating their theories the British existential analysts have made use of a number of terms, some of their own creation, whilst others are also used by Sartre. This rather technical and esoteric language creates a density in some of their writing which obscures the importance of what is being said; in my view, the value of Laing and Cooper’s book Reason and Violence is much reduced by their over-reliance on such terms and it is a pity that what one senses to be important ideas are couched in language which requires a good deal of deciphering before it becomes intelligible. If this particular book had been in existence at the time Orwell was preparing his essay “Politics and the English Language” it would have provided him with some remarkable cautionary extracts.
The British existentialists make use of two words, series and nexus, in differentiating between kinds of group—and two words, praxis and process, which describe group dynamics or the relationships between group members. A series is typically, a human association on negative grounds—for example a bus queue in which the sole link between persons is a common desire to travel on the bus; each person in the queue being “one too many” for the others. Also regarded as series are persons united solely on the basis of opposition to some shared concept: anti-semites sharing only their hatred of Jews, or one could perhaps say anarchists, united by shared opposition to the state (the only belief common to all anarchist views). A series may move towards being a group through “an act of group-synthesis” (Laing’s term). “If I think of certain others as together with me, and certain others as not together with me, I have already undertaken two acts of synthesis, resulting in we and them. However, in order that we have a group identity, it is not enough that I regard, let us say, you and him as constituting a we with myself. You and he have to perform similar acts of synthesis, each on his own behalf. In this we (me, and you, and him), each of us recognises not only our own private syntheses, but also the syntheses that each of the others makes.”[29]
The distinctive qualities of the nexus are that each person acknowPraxis and process are both terms used by Sartre. Basically, praxis is what is done by someone: “deeds done by doers”, “the acts of an individual or group”; whilst process refers to “what just happens”, activity not intended by anyone and of which no one person in a group may be aware.
The position of the person within the group will affect his idea of himself—of who he is. In the same way his view of others in the group affects their definitions of themselves. And again, his behaviour will be affected by his idea of what other people make of him. As a person moves during even one day, from group to group, from one mode of association to another, he must adapt himself to each context: “Each group requires more or less radical internal transformation of the persons who comprise it. Consider the metamorphoses that the one man may go through in one day . . . family man, speck of crowd dust, functionary in the organisation, friend. These are not simply different roles: each is a whole past and present and future, offering differing options and constraints, different degrees of change or inertia, different kinds of closeness and distance, different sets of rights and obligations, different pledges and promises.”[31]
Dr. Laing’s second book The Self and Others deals with the way in which a person is affected by his situation in a “nexus” of others, in particular within the family. “The others either can contribute to the person’s self-fulfilment, or they can be a potent factor in his losing himself (alienation) even to the point of madness.” He asserts his belief that “fantasy is a mode of experience” and that relationships on a fantasy level are “as basic to all human relatedness as the interactions that most people most of the time are more aware of.”
What happens in the families of “schizophrenics”? It is important to emphasise that it is not the thesis of these workers that the family rather than the individual is “ill”. A group is not an organism—even though it may appear to be one to its members or to observers outside it. A human group of whatever size, does not possess either a body or a mind that can be either well or ill. In the family, a person’s self can be either confirmed or disconfirmed by the actions and influence—including influence in “fantasy”—of others in the family nexus. Mystification of a person can be carried so far that all genuine expressions of independent development are denied validity. “In the families of schizophrenic patients intentions, which link up with the ‘psychotic acts’ of the patient are denied, or even, their antithesis asserted so that the patient’s actions have the appearance of pure process unrelated to praxis and may even be experienced by him as such.”[32] In the moving final section of The Divided Self (called “The Ghost of the Weed- “The patient was a good, normal, healthy child; until she gradually began
- “to be bad, to do or say things that caused great distress, and which were on the whole ‘put down’ to naughtiness or badness, until
- “this went beyond all tolerable limits so that she could only be regarded as completely mad.”
What was seen by the mother as her daughter’s “good” period, in infancy and early childhood, she described with such remarks as “she gave no trouble”, “she always did what she was told”. Laing comments that what to the mother were signs of goodness, were signs that the child had never been permitted to become “existentially alive”—in fact “being existentially dead receives the highest commendation”. The “bad” period was the time of adolescence, during which the patient made her greatest struggle towards a realisation of her own self through autonomous action but found that her efforts were continually defeated by “the complete absence of anyone in her world who could or would see some sense in her point of view”. The transfer from “bad” to “mad” came as something of a relief to the rest of the family, who “blamed themselves for not realising sooner”. As the mother said: “I knew she really could not have meant the awful things she said to me. In a way, I blame myself but, in a way, I’m glad that it was an illness after all, but if only I had not waited so long before I took her to a doctor.”
In Sanity, Madness and the Family (the first volume of an uncompleted study) Drs. Laing and Esterson present extracts from interviews with members of 11 families, all of which contained daughters diagnosed as “schizophrenic”. In the Introduction to this book the authors write: “. . . we believe that we show that the experience and behaviour of schizophrenics is much more socially intelligible than has come to be supposed by most psychiatrists . . . we believe that the shift of point of view that these descriptions both embody and demand has an historical significance no less radical than the shift from a demonological to a clinical viewpoint 300 years ago.” Behaviour which is eventually interpreted by the family as a sign of madness is, they argue, the outward expression of a desperate attempt on the part of the “mad one” to “make sense of a senseless situation”—to preserve some authentic elements of personality—a struggle for autonomy, spontaneity, responsibility and “freedom”. Here is an excerpt from Laing and Esterson’s transcript of Mr. and Mrs. Gold’s account of their daughter:These writers claim, and I think demonstrate, that armed with a knowledge of the patient’s existential situation, it is possible to make sense of what “psychiatrists still by and large regard as nonsense”. For example, Julie, the patient in “The Ghost of the Weed Garden”, referred to herself whilst in her “psychotic” state as “Mrs. Taylor” and as a “tolled bell”. Dr. Laing interprets her chosen title “Mrs. Taylor” as expressing the feelings: “I’m tailor made; I’m a tailored maid; I was made, fed, clothed and tailored” and a “tolled bell” is also “the told belle” “the girl who always did what she was told”. The schizophrenic’s “delusions” of persecution are real expressions of reaction in response to real persecution and are existentially true; that is to say they are “literally true statements within the terms of reference of the individual who makes them”.††
The person is now launched on a “career” as a mental patient. He is confirmed in this role by society’s agents the psychiatrists, in collusion with the patient’s family, and by process of betrayal and degradation[34] becomes an inmate of a mental hospital, which institution embodies “a social structure which in many respects reduplicates the maddening peculiarities of the patient’s family . . . he finds psychiatrists, administrators, nurses who are his veritable parents, brothers and sisters, who play an interpersonal game which only too often resembles in the intricacies of its rules the game he failed in at home.”[35]
The existential analysts have asserted that a great deal of what passes for treatment in mental institutions is violence. Perhaps we can now begin to see what is meant by this. David Cooper in his article in Views, No. 8 quotes Sartre’s definition of violence: “The corrosive
THEORIES IN PRACTICE: “THE ANTI-HOSPITAL”
In his pamphlet Youth for Freedom (1951) Tony Gibson wrote to the effect that the chief value of Summerhill to the community lay in its having taken the general concept of what a school should be and turned it on its head. Dr. David Cooper’s unit in a large mental hospital “just north-west of London” has done very much the same thing to the general concept of the asylum. To maintain the educational parallel, Dr. Cooper’s experiment (judging from his account of it in New Society[37]) also has great relevance for those who would wish to attack the violence implicit in the customary methods of social organisation in schools.
The unit—one ward in a hospital of some 2,300 patients—opened in January, 1962, with 19 young male patients, two-thirds of whom had been diagnosed as “having” schizophrenia. They had all been previously in the insulin-coma ward. In the second year, the number of patients was increased to 30.
The programme during the first year was highly structured, with daily meetings of the whole staff-patient group, separate and regular staff meetings, occupational therapy and organised recreational activity. No “physical” treatments were used except for the occasional dose of mild tranquilliser, and there was no individual psycho-therapy; there were however regular “interviews” between therapist and patient and therapist and patient with various members of his family. After about a year, the staff became dissatisfied with the rigidities of the system and changes in the direction of greater fluidity were felt to be appropriate.
Dr. Cooper writes of two areas in which the consequent “destructuring” had remarkable effects—the traditional business of getting patients out of bed in the morning and the attitude to the provision of work and activities. “One of the commonest staff fantasies in mental hospitals is that if patients are not coerced verbally or physically into getting out of bed at a certain hour in the morning they will stay in bed until they rot away.” This fantasy, like all anxiety over punctuality, is a form of projection. For the staff, the patient represents “that frightening aspect of themselves that sometimes does not want to get out of bed in the morning and come to work.” After considerable discussion and the trial of various approaches by different staff groups it was found that if the usual “rousing procedures” were abandoned the patient did get up himself—even if he “rebelled” to the extent of remaining in bed most of the day for a week or more. “No one rotted away after all and the gain in personal autonomy seemed worth while.” Dr. Cooper relates one episode when “all the occupants of a six-bed dormitory rebelled against the community meeting by staying in bed until after 11 o’clock. One of the charge nurses went upstairs to see what was going on. One of the patients left to go to the toilet and the nurse seized the opportunity to take off his white coat (worn not as uniform but as protective clothing for certain messy jobs like washing up) and climb into the vacant bed. The patient, on his return, appreciating the irony of the situation, had little option but to take the vacated ‘staff role’, put on the white coat and get the others out of bed.”
The motivating fantasy or belief behind the provision of work and “occupational therapy” activities is frequently that this in some way protects the patients from the eroding effects of institutionalisation. But Dr. Cooper observes: “The bitter truth is that if they submissivelyThe workers in the unit were faced with conflicting pressures—pressures to conform with the customary approaches facing them in social systems and relationships outside the unit (professional advancement and willingness to conform to some extent going together)—and contrary pressure from within the unit itself. This again resulted in tension which obliged them to face the need for “commitment one way or the other”.
The position of the experimental ward inside the framework of the large hospital prompted the growth of fantastic and distorted attitudes towards the unit in the minds of senior staff members working outside it; this indicated the deep challenge which the new approach made to their more traditional concepts. For example an incident one night, in which an hysterical girl patient was helped back to her ward by a male friend was “processed” by the communications system until in its final form, it had become a case of attempted sexual assault.
An assessment of the success of the “anti-hospital” in terms of “results” (usually measured in such cases by the incidence of re-admission) would not be any more meaningful than a judgement on Summerhill based simply on the pupil’s success rate in public examinations. The criterion of re-admission rates is also inadequate in that staff encouraged patients to return after discharge if they felt that a return to the unit would be of value to them. Nevertheless, even by this standard the “anti-hospital” results compare favourably with those achieved by more widely accepted methods—17 per cent of patients being re-admitted during a one-year period following discharge. In the issue of the British Medical Journal which included these results Dr. Cooper stated his belief that the experiment has established “at leastAs a postscript to the foregoing, I can deal only sketchily with an intriguing aspect of the work of the British existentialists—their ideas on the nature of “madness” itself. A recurrent theme in R. D. Laing’s writing is his emphasis on the disastrously narrow field of experience which is credited in contemporary life, as “reality”. “We are far more out of touch with even the nearest approaches of the infinite reaches of inner space, than we now are with the reaches of outer space. . . . We are so out of touch with this realm that many people can now argue seriously that it does not exist.”[39] It is no surprise that Dr. Laing has spoken on the power of the drug LSD to extend the boundaries of reality for those who make use of it responsibly. In The Divided Self he cites the value of the Prophetic Books of William Blake and (in The Self and Others) relates Blake to his previous description of a “psychotic”: “Blake’s position seems to me to have been this. Single ‘vision’ (one modality of experience) is death. This is what most people regard as sanity.” He also charts in this book and in other articles, the dualism implicit in the idea of fantasy to be found in most psycho-analytic works and in the minds of a good many psychiatrists: “A very confused dualistic philosophy of psychical and physical, inner and outer, mental and physical.” It is the opinion of Laing and Cooper that what is clinically described as “a schizophrenic breakdown” may be the onset in the individual of a voyage into the world of inner space and time. The word “inner” is misleading, suggesting a place located “inside” the person; as they use the word it refers to “our own personal idiom of experiencing our bodies, other people, the animate and inanimate world: imagination, dreams, fantasy . . .”. And far from being a “disease” this process, or “voyage”, may well be the path to greater awareness, the crisis of the individual’s struggle to realise himself as a person, even—the onset of sanity! (Dr. Cooper has suggested that it may be “when people start to become sane that they enter the mental hospital”). A person undergoing this experience may well be “difficult for others” and is in need of special care—but not “treatment” in “the quite bizarrely incongruous context of the mental hospital”. Those who care for him should assume the role of guides—and people capable of providing this help will very probably be those who have themselves been through similar experiences: “We need a place where people who have travelled further and, consequently, may be more lost than psychiatrists and other sane people, can find their way further into inner space and time, and back again . . . the person will be guided with full social encouragement and sanction into inner space and time, by people who have been there and back again. Psychiatrically, this would appear as ex-patients helping future patients go mad.”[40]
No fully autonomous unit in which this process can take place exists at the present moment,††† but we can deduce from the “anti-
CRITICISM AND CONCLUSIONS
The only extended criticism known to me of the work and ideas of these British psychiatrists is an article by B. A. Farrell called “The Logic of Existential Analysis” which appeared in New Society (1.10.65). This writer argues that the existentialists have dismissed orthodox views on the causes and treatment of schizophrenia on inadequate grounds and also make logically unwarrantable deductions from their research into the families of schizophrenics. Referring to the claim of Laing and Esterson that they have made the “symptoms” of schizophrenia intelligible, he makes the point that even if they are successful in doing this, making the symptoms intelligible is not the same thing as establishing truth for their hypothesis. Farrell comments that “this would be a trivial point to make” if we had other grounds for believing that the narratives were true. In relation to their suggestions for treatment he asks for evidence that units of the “anti-hospital” type produce results “as good as, or better than, the traditional methods”. In conclusion he advises them that some of the opposition to their work might not have been so vehement had they avoided “abusive” and “intemperate” language in their references to the Establishment; and also that “they would help themselves if they could avoid giving the impression that they had fallen in love with their schizophrenic patients. . . .”
Correspondents in subsequent issues suggested some answers to these criticisms. Commenting on Mr. Farrell’s remark on the lack of supportive evidence, Dr. John Bowlby wrote: “Although Dr. Laing’s is the only psychiatric group in this country publishing material of its sort, in the United States there are several. The two best known are the group at the National Institute of Mental Health . . . and the one at Palo Alto. . . . Each of these research groups has used methods and reported findings essentially similar to those of Dr. Laing. Some of their most recent reports . . . are of projects that at critical points in the procedure are ‘blind’ in just the way that Mr. Farrell rightly requests. In addition a number of findings derived from quite other methods are supportive. . . . There is thus substantial evidence derived from more than one method in support of the Laing type of hypothesis. . . . When compared with evidence advanced to support other types of hypothesis, it is not unimpressive. On the one hand it is far more substantial than any yet offered in support of psycho-analytic theories, whether traditional or Kleinian, and, on the other, more consistent than that supporting a genetic-biochemical type of theory” (my italics).[41]
I have already made some reference to the “results”, in terms of re-admissions, of the “anti-hospital” which were published in theMr. Farrell’s final charge is valuable in that it draws attention to the basis of the method of existential analysis as described and practised by Dr. Laing and his colleagues. I do not think that Dr. Laing would wish to deny that “love” is involved in his attitude towards his patients and their predicament. In The Divided Self he writes of the act of empathy—this is not a strong enough word—that is required if the therapist is to understand the patient’s existential position. “I think it is clear that by ‘understanding’ I do not mean a purely intellectual process. For understanding one might say love.”[42] In making this attempt the therapist “draws on his own psychotic possibilities”. Although not a direct parallel, one is reminded of Homer Lane’s attitude towards emotionally disturbed “delinquent” adolescents and his dictum of “being on their side” even when their actions were most anti-social. A concept that recurs in a similar way in Dr. Laing’s writing is to “let the other be”: “The main agent in uniting the patient, in allowing the pieces to come together and cohere is the physician’s love, a love that recognises the patient’s total being, and accepts it, with no strings attached.”[43]
As I hope I have succeeded in indicating in this article, the work of Drs. Laing, Cooper and Esterson constitutes far more than just another theory of what causes “schizophrenia”; a correspondent in New Society characterised it as “an exploration of the necessary conditions for a fully human relationship”.[44]
Dr. Laing has suggested that the reason why exploration of the “inner” world of the self is invalidated by society as “madness” is that such experience is subversive. “And it is subversive because it is real.”[45] Deified destructive illusions—“the health of sterling”, “the Red menace”, “the interests of the State”—are the stage-props of normal social life and these phantoms are confirmed as “reality” by all the resources available. Because the vast majority of people act in terms of these negations “we find ourselves threatened by extermination that will be reciprocal, that no one wishes, that everyone fears, that may just happen to us ‘because’ no one knows how to stop it. . . . Everyone will by carrying out orders. Where do they come from? Always from elsewhere. . . .”[46] Dr. Cooper has also described this tragic condition: “The myth of Thanatos is a self-actualizing phantasy. The bomb really did drop on Hiroshima. . . . The basic paradox that we live is that mankind needs illusions but the illusions it needs destroy it. Even through relatively innocuous or ‘good’ illusions we imprison ourselves metaphysically and then find we have built real prison walls (perhaps around someone else).”[47]
I hope that, as Dr. Laing has hinted, their future work will involve and imply further criticism in depth, of our society; if this is the case it will have direct relevance for contemporary anarchism (notwithstanding the association of these writers with a form of Marxism). In conclusion, I would risk the statement that the body of work they have
** An article in The Observer (4.9.66) announced the formation of “Project 70”—“a plan to rescue mentally normal old people from the wards of mental hospitals.”
*** This may have been an allusion to a case which was receiving some publicity at that time. Zenya Belov, a student, was confined in a Russian mental institution around September, 1965—and he is presumably still there. It was alleged that he had shown “schizophrenic symptoms” (“drawing diagrams, trying to reorganise the world graphically”) but the only “symptoms” evident to the British students who were with him shortly before the onset of “illness” were his “unorthodox and reformist political views”.
† References to a letter from Brenda Jordan in Peace News (17.6.66).
†† See also Laing’s interpretation of the statements of a schizophrenic from the original account in Kraepelin’s Lectures on Clinical Psychiatry, 1905 (pp. 29-31 The Divided Self). Laing writes: “What does this patient seem to be doing? Surely he is carrying on a dialogue between his own parodied version of Kraepelin, and his own defiant rebelling self. ‘You want to know that too? I tell you who is being measured and is measured and shall be measured. I know all that, and I could tell you, but I do not want to’.” Laing comments: “This seems to be plain enough talk.”
††† Since this was written an article has appeared. “Schizophrenia as a way of life”, by Ruth Abel (Guardian, 4.10.66), describing a “fully autonomous unit” for “schizophrenics” established by Drs. Laing, Esterson and Cooper at Kingsley Hall in London. This project is financed by The Philadelphia Association and it seems that two new centres have been opened during the last few months in North London, and it is hoped that these are only the first of “a chain of communities”.
David Cooper, “Sartre on Genet”, New Left Review, No. 25.
R. D. Laing, The Politics of Experience and the Bird of Paradise, Penguin Books, Autumn, 1966.
R. D. Laing, H. Phillipson, A. R. Lee, Interpersonal Perception: A Theory and a Method, London, Tavistock, 1966.
T. S. Szasz, The Myth of Mental Illness, London, Seeker and Warburg, 1962.
Carl R. Rogers, On Becoming a Person, London, Constable & Co., 1961.
- ↑ Robert G. Olson, An Introduction to Existentialism, New York, Dover Publications, 1962, p. 52.
- ↑ ibid., p. 105 (a reference to an episode in Being and Nothingness, p. 495).
- ↑ J.-P. Sartre, Situations III, Paris, Gallimard, 1949 (quoted by Olson, p. 121).
- ↑ Olson, op. cit., p. 119.
- ↑ J.-P. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, London, Methuen, 1956, pp. 461-2.
- ↑ ibid., pp. 471-75 (quoted by Olson, p. 121).
- ↑ The first part of R. D. Laing’s The Self and Others is a lucid argument against the basic concepts of traditional psycho-analysis.
- ↑ “Massacre of the Innocents”, Peace News, 22nd January, 1965.
- ↑ BBC “Panorama” on “Mental Health”, 6th June, 1966.
- ↑ David Cooper, “The Anti-Hospital: An Experiment in Psychiatry”, New Society, 11th March, 1965.
- ↑ David Cooper, “Violence in Psychiatry”, Views, No. 8, Summer, 1965.
- ↑ ibid.
- ↑ Part of a letter by Pierre-Joseph Brie, “Insanity and the Egg”, Peace News, 1st July, 1966.
- ↑ T. S. Szasz, “Politics and Mental Health”, American Journal of Psychiatry, No. 115 (1958) (quoted by Erving Goffman in Asylums, p. 509).
- ↑ Erving Goffman, Asylums—Essays on the Social Situation of Mental Patients and Other Inmates, New York, Anchor Books, 1961, pp. 363-4.
- ↑ ibid., p. 354.
- ↑ ibid., p. 135.
- ↑ ibid., p. 380.
- ↑ For a reconstruction of a psychiatric interrogation see “The Case Conference”, Views, No. 11, Summer, 1966. Elias Canetti has written that “questioning is a forcible intrusion. When used as an instrument of power, it is like a knife cutting into the flesh of the victim. . . . The most blatant tyranny is the one that asks the most questions” (Crowds and Power, Gollancz, 1962).
- ↑ A sentence of Dr. Joshua Dierer’s, speaking at the World Federation of Mental Health, 1960 (quoted by Colin Ward in “Where The Shoe Pinches”, anarchy 4).
- ↑ Goffman, op. cit., p. 384.
- ↑ An estimate made by the Swiss psychiatrist E. Bleuler, quoted by David Cooper in “The Anti-Hospital”.
- ↑ P. Rube, “Healing Process in Schizophrenia”, Journal of Nervous and Mental Diseases, 1948 (quoted by John Linsie in “Schizophrenia: A Social Disease”, anarchy 24).
- ↑ R. D. Laing, “What is Schizophrenia?”, New Left Review, No. 28.
- ↑ R. D. Laing and A. Esterson, Sanity, Madness and the Family, London, Tavistock, 1964.
- ↑ R. D. Laing, “What is Schizophrenia?”, op. cit.
- ↑ David Cooper, “The Anti-Hospital”, op. cit.
- ↑ David Cooper, Violence in Psychiatry, Views, No. 8.
- ↑ R. D. Laing, “Us and Them”, Views, No. 11.
- ↑ R. D. Laing and A. Esterson, op. cit.
- ↑ R. D. Laing, “Us and Them”, op. cit.
- ↑ David Cooper, “Two Types of Rationality”, New Left Review, No. 29.
- ↑ op. cit., p. 155.
- ↑ Erving Goffman in Asylums makes use of the term “career” to denote “the social strand” of a person’s life inaugurated at the moment of his definition as a mental patient; “betrayal funnel” to describe the circuit of figures (relatives, psychiatrists, etc.) whose interactions end with the patient’s confinement in the 374asylum, and “degradation ceremonial” for the psychiatric examination preceding the patient’s admission.
- ↑ David Cooper, “Violence in Psychiatry”, op. cit.
- ↑ ibid.
- ↑ New Society, 11th March, 1965.
- ↑ British Medical Journal, No. 5476, p. 1462.
- ↑ R. D. Laing, “What is Schizophrenia?”, op. cit.
- ↑ ibid.
- ↑ Extract from letter in New Society, 4th November, 1965.
- ↑ R. D. Laing, The Divided Self—An Existential Study in Sanity and Madness, London, Tavistock, 1960 (Pelican Books, 1965).
- ↑ ibid., p. 165.
- ↑ A phrase from a letter by J. D. Ingleby (Applied Psychology Research Unit, Cambridge), New Society, 28th October, 1965.
- ↑ “A Ten Day Voyage”, Views, No. 8.
- ↑ “Us and Them”, op. cit.
- ↑ “Freud Revisited”—a review of Herbert Marcuse’s Eros and Civilization, New Left Review, No. 20.