Difference between revisions of "Anarchy 70/Libertarian Psychiatry: an introduction to existential analysis"
imported>Ivanhoe |
imported>Ivanhoe |
||
Line 17: | Line 17: | ||
{{p|s1}}{{sc|This art­icle aims to draw at­ten­tion}} to the work of a group of British psy­chi­atrists of whom the best known are {{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}} and {{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}}. They have achieved some no­tori­ety in this country because of the ex­tent of their di­ver­gence, both in theory and prac­tice, from cur­rent psy­chi­atric ortho­doxy{{dash}}and par­tic­u­larly as a con­sequence of their refer­ences to the pre­val­ent {{qq|treat­ment}} of the men­tally ill as {{qq|viol­ence}}. As a teacher, I am not qual­ified to at­tempt more than an out­line of their ideas as under­stood by me, after read­ing their books and art­icles and some related studies. But the im­plica­tions of the work of the British ex­ist­en­tial­ist group ex­tend beyond the limits of psy­chi­atry{{dash}}and the very gener­ality of their as­ser­tions in­vites a re­sponse from the layman. Writing of the pro­cess which in their view results in the ul­ti­mate in­val­id­a­tion of persons through the label­ling of them as {{qq|mad}}, Laing asks: {{qq|… what func­tion does this pro­ced­ure serve for the civic order? These ques­tions are only begin­ning to be asked, much less answered. … So­cially, this work must now move to further under­stand­ing … of the mean­ing of all this within the larger con­text of the civic order of so­ciety{{dash}}that is, of the ''polit­ical'' order, of the ways persons exer­cise control and power over one an­other.}} (''{{w|New Left Review|New_Left_Review}}'', No. 28.) Anarch­ism is about just this, and any theory, from what­ever dis­cipline, which leads to a ques­tion­ing of the polit­ical order of so­ciety should have rel­ev­ance for us{{dash}}and we should know some­thing about it. | {{p|s1}}{{sc|This art­icle aims to draw at­ten­tion}} to the work of a group of British psy­chi­atrists of whom the best known are {{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}} and {{w|David Cooper|David_Cooper_(psychiatrist)}}. They have achieved some no­tori­ety in this country because of the ex­tent of their di­ver­gence, both in theory and prac­tice, from cur­rent psy­chi­atric ortho­doxy{{dash}}and par­tic­u­larly as a con­sequence of their refer­ences to the pre­val­ent {{qq|treat­ment}} of the men­tally ill as {{qq|viol­ence}}. As a teacher, I am not qual­ified to at­tempt more than an out­line of their ideas as under­stood by me, after read­ing their books and art­icles and some related studies. But the im­plica­tions of the work of the British ex­ist­en­tial­ist group ex­tend beyond the limits of psy­chi­atry{{dash}}and the very gener­ality of their as­ser­tions in­vites a re­sponse from the layman. Writing of the pro­cess which in their view results in the ul­ti­mate in­val­id­a­tion of persons through the label­ling of them as {{qq|mad}}, Laing asks: {{qq|… what func­tion does this pro­ced­ure serve for the civic order? These ques­tions are only begin­ning to be asked, much less answered. … So­cially, this work must now move to further under­stand­ing … of the mean­ing of all this within the larger con­text of the civic order of so­ciety{{dash}}that is, of the ''polit­ical'' order, of the ways persons exer­cise control and power over one an­other.}} (''{{w|New Left Review|New_Left_Review}}'', No. 28.) Anarch­ism is about just this, and any theory, from what­ever dis­cipline, which leads to a ques­tion­ing of the polit­ical order of so­ciety should have rel­ev­ance for us{{dash}}and we should know some­thing about it. | ||
− | {{tab}}Dr. Laing has written that his main intel­lec­tual in­debt­ed­ness is to {{qq|the {{w|ex­ist­en­tial|Existentialism}} tradi­tion}}{{dash|{{w|Kierke­gaard|Søren_Kierkegaard}}, {{w|Jaspers|Karl_Jaspers}}, {{w|Heideg­ger|Martin_Heidegger}}, {{w|Bins­wanger|Ludwig_Binswanger}}, {{w|Tillich|Paul_Tillich}} and {{w|Sartre|Jean-Paul_Sartre}}}}and of these there is no doubt that Sartre{{s}} in­flu­ence has been the great­est. The British ana­lysts have clearly worked out their own the­or­et­ical basis and in many in­stan­ces have de­veloped Sartre{{s}} ideas rather than merely adopted them as they stand. I am not cer­tain, for ex­ample how com­pletely Laing and Cooper share Sartre{{s}} total re­jec­tion of the con­cept of {{qq|the un­con­scious}}. However, their book {{l|''Reason and Viol­ence'': ''A Decade of Sartre{{s}} Philo­sophy'' 1950-1960|http://laingsociety.org/biblio/randv.htm}} (Tavistock, 1964) opens with a com­pli­ment­ary pre­fat­ory note from the French philo­sopher{{dash|I believe this is an un­usual honour for a book about his ideas}}and this ''im­prim­atur'' sug­gests that what­ever their diver­gen­cies, they can­not be basic. | + | {{tab}}Dr. Laing has written that his main intel­lec­tual in­debt­ed­ness is to {{qq|the {{w|ex­ist­en­tial|Existentialism}} tradi­tion}}{{dash|{{w|Kierke­gaard|Søren_Kierkegaard}}, {{w|Jaspers|Karl_Jaspers}}, {{w|Heideg­ger|Martin_Heidegger}}, {{w|Bins­wanger|Ludwig_Binswanger}}, {{w|Tillich|Paul_Tillich}} and {{w|Sartre|Jean-Paul_Sartre}}}}and of these there is no doubt that Sartre{{s}} in­flu­ence has been the great­est. The British ana­lysts have clearly worked out their own the­or­et­ical basis and in many in­stan­ces have de­veloped Sartre{{s}} ideas rather than merely adopted them as they stand. I am not cer­tain, for ex­ample, how com­pletely Laing and Cooper share Sartre{{s}} total re­jec­tion of the con­cept of {{qq|the un­con­scious}}. However, their book {{l|''Reason and Viol­ence'': ''A Decade of Sartre{{s}} Philo­sophy'' 1950-1960|http://laingsociety.org/biblio/randv.htm}} (Tavistock, 1964) opens with a com­pli­ment­ary pre­fat­ory note from the French philo­sopher{{dash|I believe this is an un­usual honour for a book about his ideas}}and this ''im­prim­atur'' sug­gests that what­ever their diver­gen­cies, they can­not be basic. |
{{tab}}In [[Anarchy 44|{{sc|anarchy}} 44]] J.-P. Sartre is re­ferred to as {{qq|one of the fore­most anarch­ist moral­ists}} ([[Author:Ian Vine|Ian Vine]]: {{qq|[[Anarchy 44/The morality of anarchism|The Moral­ity of Anarch­ism]]}}). This de­scrip­tion com­pares in­triguingly with an­other, made by the so­cial­ist {{w|Alasdair<!-- 'Alisdair' in original --> MacIntyre|Alasdair_MacIntyre}}, re­view­ing Sartre{{s}} book ''{{w|The Prob­lem of Method|Search_for_a_Method}}'' in ''{{w|Peace News|Peace_News}}''. He re­fers to Sartre as a newly found {{qq|spokes­man of genius}} for {{qq|ersatz {{w|bolshev­iks|Bolsheviks}}}} and {{qq|im­it­a­tion anarch­ists}}. Not know­ing MacIntyre{{s}} idea of the genu­ine art­icle, this does not ex­actly rule the French­man out and I believe his work may well just­ify a place on an anarch­ist{{s}} book list. Writing with par­tic­u­lar refer­ence to Sartre{{s}} recent work, MacIntyre notes that Sartre can offer no bonds, other than re­cip­roc­ally threat­ened viol­ence and terror, of suf­fi­cient strength to main­tain the co­he­sion of human groups in a world of {{qq|im­pos­sibly indi­vidual­ist indi­viduals}}. Per­haps a spokes­man for {{w|Stirner­ites|Philosophy_of_Max_Stirner}}? Never­the­less, the poten­ti­alit­ies of Sartre{{s}} philo­sophy as a basis for anarch­ism are in­cid­ental to my pur­pose here. | {{tab}}In [[Anarchy 44|{{sc|anarchy}} 44]] J.-P. Sartre is re­ferred to as {{qq|one of the fore­most anarch­ist moral­ists}} ([[Author:Ian Vine|Ian Vine]]: {{qq|[[Anarchy 44/The morality of anarchism|The Moral­ity of Anarch­ism]]}}). This de­scrip­tion com­pares in­triguingly with an­other, made by the so­cial­ist {{w|Alasdair<!-- 'Alisdair' in original --> MacIntyre|Alasdair_MacIntyre}}, re­view­ing Sartre{{s}} book ''{{w|The Prob­lem of Method|Search_for_a_Method}}'' in ''{{w|Peace News|Peace_News}}''. He re­fers to Sartre as a newly found {{qq|spokes­man of genius}} for {{qq|ersatz {{w|bolshev­iks|Bolsheviks}}}} and {{qq|im­it­a­tion anarch­ists}}. Not know­ing MacIntyre{{s}} idea of the genu­ine art­icle, this does not ex­actly rule the French­man out and I believe his work may well just­ify a place on an anarch­ist{{s}} book list. Writing with par­tic­u­lar refer­ence to Sartre{{s}} recent work, MacIntyre notes that Sartre can offer no bonds, other than re­cip­roc­ally threat­ened viol­ence and terror, of suf­fi­cient strength to main­tain the co­he­sion of human groups in a world of {{qq|im­pos­sibly indi­vidual­ist indi­viduals}}. Per­haps a spokes­man for {{w|Stirner­ites|Philosophy_of_Max_Stirner}}? Never­the­less, the poten­ti­alit­ies of Sartre{{s}} philo­sophy as a basis for anarch­ism are in­cid­ental to my pur­pose here. | ||
Line 29: | Line 29: | ||
{{tab}}{{qq|Man can­not be some­times slave and some­times free; he is wholly and forever free, or he is not free at all.}} | {{tab}}{{qq|Man can­not be some­times slave and some­times free; he is wholly and forever free, or he is not free at all.}} | ||
− | <div style="text-align:right;">{{w|Sartre|Jean-Paul_Sartre}}: ''{{w|Being and No­thing­ness|Being_and_Nothingness}}''</div> | + | <div style="text-align:right;">{{w|Sartre|Jean-Paul_Sartre}}: ''{{w|Being and No­thing­ness|Being_and_Nothingness}}''.</div> |
− | {{tab}}The con­cept of free­dom at the core of ex­ist­en­tial­ism is very dif­fer­ent from what I take to be the com­mon under­stand­ing of the term. In gen­eral usage, a man is free in as much as he can achieve his chosen ends with a min­imum of effort. Simil­arly, a man{{s}} free­dom is re­duced as the ob­stacles between his de­sires and chosen ends are in­creased. Free­dom is re­garded as a measur­able quant­ity; one may have a lot or a little of it, and it can be taken away{{dash}}or even {{qq|given}}. The anarch­ist{{s}} hypo­thet­ical destin­a­tion, the {{qq|free}} so­ciety, may often be thought of in the sense of an har­mo­ni­ous envir­on­ment in which all re­mov­able ob­stacles between man{{s}} de­sires and their ful­fil­ment have been elim­in­ated. But for Sartre, man is totally free by reason of his very being as man, and ob­stacles between de­sires and chosen ends are of no rel­ev­ance. To use a favoured ex­ist­en­tial­ist phrase, man is free by onto­lo­gical neces­sity. But his free­dom rests, within this con­cept, in his total re­spons­ibil­ity in the face of un­deter­mined choice and in his recog­ni­tion of the in­escap­able ob­lig­a­tion to choose. An intuit­ive aware­ness of this re­spons­ib­il­ity{{dash|per­haps pro­voked by some sort of {{qq|ex­treme situ­a­tion}}}}gives rise to what Sartre calls {{qq|the anguish of free­dom}}. It is our fate to be free. {{qq|… One must always de­cide for one­self and efforts to shift the burden of re­spons­ib­il­ity upon others are neces­sar­ily self-<wbr>de­feat­ing. Not to choose is also to choose, for even if we de­liver our power of de­ci­sion to others, we are still re­spons­ible for having done so. It is always the indi­vidual who de­cides that others will choose for him.}}<ref>Robert G. Olson, ''An Intro­duc­tion to Ex­ist­en­tial­ism'', New York, Dover Publi­ca­tions, 1962, p. 52.</ref> In so far as we are free in our choices, we {{qq|create}} the ob­stacles that lie between our pro­ject and its ful­fil­ment: {{qq|an in­sig­ni­fic­ant public of­fi­cial in {{w|Mont-de-Marsan|Mont-de-Marsan}} without means may not have the op­por­tun­ity to go to {{w|New York| | + | {{tab}}The con­cept of free­dom at the core of ex­ist­en­tial­ism is very dif­fer­ent from what I take to be the com­mon under­stand­ing of the term. In gen­eral usage, a man is free in as much as he can achieve his chosen ends with a min­imum of effort. Simil­arly, a man{{s}} free­dom is re­duced as the ob­stacles between his de­sires and chosen ends are in­creased. Free­dom is re­garded as a measur­able quant­ity; one may have a lot or a little of it, and it can be taken away{{dash}}or even {{qq|given}}. The anarch­ist{{s}} hypo­thet­ical destin­a­tion, the {{qq|free}} so­ciety, may often be thought of in the sense of an har­mo­ni­ous envir­on­ment in which all re­mov­able ob­stacles between man{{s}} de­sires and their ful­fil­ment have been elim­in­ated. But for Sartre, man is totally free by reason of his very being as man, and ob­stacles between de­sires and chosen ends are of no rel­ev­ance. To use a favoured ex­ist­en­tial­ist phrase, man is free by onto­lo­gical neces­sity. But his free­dom rests, within this con­cept, in his total re­spons­ibil­ity in the face of un­deter­mined choice and in his recog­ni­tion of the in­escap­able ob­lig­a­tion to choose. An intuit­ive aware­ness of this re­spons­ib­il­ity{{dash|per­haps pro­voked by some sort of {{qq|ex­treme situ­a­tion}}}}gives rise to what Sartre calls {{qq|the anguish of free­dom}}. It is our fate to be free. {{qq|… One must always de­cide for one­self and efforts to shift the burden of re­spons­ib­il­ity upon others are neces­sar­ily self-<wbr>de­feat­ing. Not to choose is also to choose, for even if we de­liver our power of de­ci­sion to others, we are still re­spons­ible for having done so. It is always the indi­vidual who de­cides that others will choose for him.}}<ref>Robert G. Olson, ''An Intro­duc­tion to Ex­ist­en­tial­ism'', New York, Dover Publi­ca­tions, 1962, p. 52.</ref> In so far as we are free in our choices, we {{qq|create}} the ob­stacles that lie between our pro­ject and its ful­fil­ment: {{qq|an in­sig­ni­fic­ant public of­fi­cial in {{w|Mont-de-Marsan|Mont-de-Marsan}} without means may not have the op­por­tun­ity to go to {{w|New York|New_York_City}} if that be his ambi­tion. But the ob­stacles which stand in his way would not exist as ob­stacles were it not for his free choice of values: in this case, his desire to go {{p|355}}to New York.}}<ref>ibid., p. 105 (a refer­ence to an epis­ode in ''Being and No­thing­ness'', p. 495).</ref> Even though human free­dom, in his view, is total, Sartre ad­mits of a sense in which it may be spoken of in terms of degree. A man may be said to become {{qq|more free}} as his con­scious­ness of total free­dom and re­spons­ib­il­ity in­creases; and cer­tain situ­a­tions in life can crystal­lize this aware­ness. In an ap­par­ently cryptic para­graph in ''Being and No­thing­ness'' Sartre de­scribes the {{w|German Oc­cupa­tion of France|German_military_administration_in_occupied_France_during_World_War_II}} during the last {{w|war|World_War_II}} as such a situ­a­tion. {{qq|… the choice that each of us made of his life and his being was an au­then­tic choice because it was made face to face with death, because it could always have been ex­pressed in these terms: {{q|Rather death than …}}.}}<ref>{{w|J.-P. Sartre|Jean-Paul_Sartre}}, ''Situations III'', Paris, Gallimard, 1949 (quoted by {{popup|Olson|Robert G. Olson. An Introduction to Existentialism.}}, p. 121).</ref> But the issue is not just one of an in­creased sense of re­spons­ib­il­ity for our day-<wbr>to-<wbr>day options{{dash}}for in­stance in de­cid­ing upon a change in oc­cu­pa­tion, or merely which book to read next; most sig­ni­fic­antly ''we choose our­selves'', and our day-<wbr>to-<wbr>day de­ci­sions neces­sarily re­flect this primary choice we have made. We are what we have chosen to be. All our sub­sequent modes of action are re­lated to this original {{qq|project-<wbr>of-<wbr>being}}, {{qq|Freely chosen at the moment one wrenches one­self away from the in-<wbr>itself to create one{{s}} own world}}<ref>{{popup|Olson|Robert G. Olson}}, {{popup|op. cit.|opere citato: cited above}}, p. 119.</ref> (the in-<wbr>itself: the world of things). This event I take to be com­par­able with what R. D. Laing calls {{qq|ex­ist­en­tial birth}} which, he sug­gests, is as essen­tial for a fully human ex­ist­ence as the bio­lo­gical birth which it nor­mally follows.{{ref|aster|*}} It is only in rela­tion to this funda­mental choice, the indi­vidual{{s}} original {{qq|pro­ject-<wbr>of-<wbr>being}} that his later beha­viour can be fully under­stood. The plaus­ibil­ity of this basic idea is not in­creased by Sartre{{s}} denial of the divi­sion of the self into con­scious and un­con­scious modes; the idea of a tooth­less infant con­sciously de­termin­ing its future life­style and pur­pose is at first thought ab­surd. But whilst ex­pli­citly deny­ing valid­ity to the {{qq|un­con­scious}} Sartre does separ­ate con­scious­ness into {{qq|re­flect­ive}} and {{qq|non-<wbr>re­flect­ive}} levels, and it is at the non-<wbr>re­flect­ive level that this funda­mental choice is made. He stresses that this original choice is in no way de­liber­ate: {{qq|This is not because it would be less con­scious or less ex­plicit than a de­liber­a­tion but, on the con­trary, because it is the found­a­tion of all de­liber­a­tion and because … a de­liber­a­tion re­quires an inter­pret­a­tion in terms of an original choice.}}<ref>{{w|J.-P. Sartre|Jean-Paul_Sartre}}, {{w|''Being and No­thing­ness''|Being_and_Nothingness}}, London, Methuen, 1956, pp. 461-2.</ref> The con­cepts of {{qq|au­then­ti­city}} and its ap­proxim­ate op­po­site {{qq|bad-<wbr>faith}} are in a sense under­stand­able as judge­ments (al­though Sartre claims only to use these terms de­script­ively) upon the degree of con­cord­ance between the choices of our re­flect­ive con­scious­ness and our original pro­ject-<wbr>of-<wbr>being. In a pas­sage which bears di­rectly upon ex­ist­en­tial ana­lysis he writes that a man {{qq|can make vol­un­tary de­ci­sions which are op­posed to the funda­mental ends which he has chosen. These de­ci­sions can be only vol­un­tary{{dash}}that is, re­flect­ive. … Thus, for ex­ample, I can de­cide to cure myself of {{w|stutter­ing|Stuttering}}. I can even {{p|256}}suc­ceed in it. … In fact I can ob­tain a result by using merely tech­nical methods. … But these re­sults will only dis­place the in­firm­ity from which I suf­fer; an­other will arise in its place and will in its own way ex­press the total end which I pur­sue. … It is the same with these cures as it is with the cure of {{w|hys­teria|Hysteria}} by {{w|elec­tric shock treat­ment|Electroconvulsive_therapy}}. We know that this ther­apy can effect the dis­ap­pear­ance of an hys­terical con­trac­tion of the leg, but as one will see some time later the con­trac­tion will ap­pear in the arm. This is because the hys­teria can be cured only as a total­ity, for it is a total pro­ject of the for-<wbr>itself}}<ref>ibid., pp. 471-75 (quoted by {{popup|Olson|Robert G. Olson}}, p. 121).</ref> (the for-<wbr>itself: the world of con­scious­ness and in­ten­tion). |
− | {{tab}}Sartre argues against the {{w|Freud­ian|Sigmund_Freud}} three-<wbr>way split of the per­sonal­ity into {{w|id, ego and super-ego|Id,_ego_and_super-ego}} and the {{w| | + | {{tab}}Sartre argues against the {{w|Freud­ian|Sigmund_Freud}} three-<wbr>way split of the per­sonal­ity into {{w|id, ego and super-ego|Id,_ego_and_super-ego}} and the {{w|psycho{{-}}ana­lytic|Psychoanalysis}} dictum of con­scious beha­viour as de­term­ined by drives, in­stincts and de­sires al­legedly eman­at­ing from the id. As Sartre{{s}} argu­ments hinge upon his stated belief in man{{s}} on­to­lo­gical free­dom, Freud{{s}} pro­ject of {{qq|de­term­ina­tion by the un­con­scious}} is met with similar ob­jec­tions to those made against other de­term­in­ist theories and I need not at­tempt to sum­mar­ise them here.<ref>The first part of {{w|R. D. Laing|R._D._Laing}}{{s}} ''The Self and Others'' is a lucid argu­ment against the basic con­cepts of tradi­tional psycho-<wbr>ana­lysis.</ref> The only valid form of ther­apy is one aimed at dis­cover­ing an indi­vidual{{s}} funda­mental pro­ject-<wbr>of-<wbr>being{{dash}}and this is the pur­pose of ex­ist­en­tial ana­lysis (or psycho-<wbr>ana­lysis; the pre­fix seems to be op­tional). {{qq|The prin­ciple of this psycho-<wbr>ana­lysis is that man is a total­ity and not a col­lec­tion; he there­fore ex­presses him­self in his total­ity in the most in­sig­ni­fic­ant and the most super­fi­cial as­pects of his con­duct}} (''Being and No­thing­ness''). Through the use of a tech­nique or method based on such as­sump­tions the ini­tially {{qq|crazy}} actions of the in­sane may be made com­pre­hens­ible{{dash}}and may even ap­pear {{qq|reason­able}} if a picture of the world in which the pa­tient lives can be as­sembled. |
{{tab}}R. D. Laing has written that {{qq|only by the most out­rage­ous viol­a­tion of our­selves have we achieved our cap­ac­ity to live in relat­ive ad­just­ment to a civil­isa­tion ap­par­ently driven to its own de­struc­tion}} and has de­scribed the {{qq|normal}} person in the present age as {{qq|a half-<wbr>crazed creature, more or less ad­justed to a mad world}}.<ref>{{qq|Mas­sacre of the In­no­cents}}, ''{{w|Peace News|Peace_News}}'', 22nd January, 1965.</ref> What is the norm that gives the gen­erally ac­cepted mean­ing to such relat­ive de­scrip­tions as {{qq|mad}}, {{qq|insane}}, {{qq|mal­ad­justed}}? And what is the sig­ni­fic­ance of what is done to the people that are dis­qual­i­fied when meas­ured against this cri­terion; the people that the mad offi­cials label as {{qq|offi­cially mad}}? | {{tab}}R. D. Laing has written that {{qq|only by the most out­rage­ous viol­a­tion of our­selves have we achieved our cap­ac­ity to live in relat­ive ad­just­ment to a civil­isa­tion ap­par­ently driven to its own de­struc­tion}} and has de­scribed the {{qq|normal}} person in the present age as {{qq|a half-<wbr>crazed creature, more or less ad­justed to a mad world}}.<ref>{{qq|Mas­sacre of the In­no­cents}}, ''{{w|Peace News|Peace_News}}'', 22nd January, 1965.</ref> What is the norm that gives the gen­erally ac­cepted mean­ing to such relat­ive de­scrip­tions as {{qq|mad}}, {{qq|insane}}, {{qq|mal­ad­justed}}? And what is the sig­ni­fic­ance of what is done to the people that are dis­qual­i­fied when meas­ured against this cri­terion; the people that the mad offi­cials label as {{qq|offi­cially mad}}? |
Revision as of 10:40, 11 August 2017
an introduction to
existential analysis
Dr. Laing has written that his main intellectual indebtedness is to “the existential tradition”—
In anarchy 44 J.-P. Sartre is referred to as “one of the foremost anarchist moralists” (Ian Vine: “The Morality of Anarchism”). This description compares intriguingly with another, made by the socialist Alasdair MacIntyre, reviewing Sartre’s book The Problem of Method in Peace News. He refers to Sartre as a newly found “spokesman of genius” for “ersatz bolsheviks” and “imitation anarchists”. Not knowing MacIntyre’s idea of the genuine article, this does not exactly rule the Frenchman out and I believe his work may well justify a place on an anarchist’s book list. Writing with particular reference to Sartre’s recent work, MacIntyre notes that Sartre can offer no bonds, other than reciprocally threatened violence and terror, of sufficient strength to maintain the cohesion of human groups in a world of “impossibly individualist individuals”. Perhaps a spokesman for Stirnerites? Nevertheless, the potentialities of Sartre’s philosophy as a basis for anarchism are incidental to my purpose here.
The first of four episodes of this essay are intended to create a setting against which existential analysis may be viewed.
“Man cannot be sometimes slave and sometimes free; he is wholly and forever free, or he is not free at all.”
Sartre argues against the Freudian three-
R. D. Laing has written that “only by the most outrageous violation of ourselves have we achieved our capacity to live in relative adjustment to a civilisation apparently driven to its own destruction” and has described the “normal” person in the present age as “a half-
“In the context of our present madness that we call normality, sanity, freedom, all our frames of reference are ambiguous and equivocal.”
By far the largest group is the third—
“Many of us, for quite some time have considered that problems of punishment and repression are most acute in the context of imprisonment. But this is not so; the really intractable problem in this sphere is that of the mental hospital.”
In his account of “de-institutionalisation” (anarchy 4) Colin Ward referred to the prison as “the most sinister of institutions” and no doubt it is. But as anarchists are aware, the state can make skilful use of the “approved” concepts of crime and criminality to divert attention from its own more grandiose but identical activities: so we should be alert to the possibility that the institutions openly labelled as prisons are not the only ones serving that function. Suppose, as Roger Moody says in his article that mental hospital and prison are “different terms for the same thing”? If there is some truth in this there is consequently an additional danger in that anything called a “hospital” has automatically a protective cocoon around it as a result of its claim to provide therapy. But surely the “voluntary” presence of many of the patients in mental hospitals ensures that they cannot have a punitive character or effect? A different approach is suggested by the American sociologist Erving Goffman: “… We must see the mental hospital, in the recent historical context in which it developed, as one among a network of institutions designed to provide a residence for various categories of socially troublesome people.”[16]
As Malatesta noted in his essay “Anarchy”, “Organs and functions are inseparable terms. Take from an organ its function, and either the organ will die, or the function will reinstate itself.” The existence of the mental hospital is justified by its function of curing the mentally ill. “The patient’s presence in the hospital is taken as prima facie evidence that he is mentally ill, since the hospitalization of these persons is what the institution is for.” A very common answer to a patient who claims he is sane is the statement: “If you aren’t sick you wouldn’t be in the hospital.”[18] One consequence of this for the person initiated into a “career” as a mental patient is that his past life will be restructured in terms of a “case history”—
Because society needs lunatics to provide it with reassurance of its own sanity, so it has need of institutions to contain them. But as with prisons, the real enemy is not the material structure—
“In the popular mind the schizophrenic is the proto-typical madman—
One psycho-analytic view is that schizophrenia is the outcome of a split between a person’s “conscious” and “subconscious” forces which in the normal state are believed to work simultaneously. Another idea—
This I hope is enough to provide some basis for R. D. Laing’s and A. Esterson’s statement in the introduction to Sanity, Madness and the Family that there is no more disputed condition in the whole field of medicine. “The one thing certain about schizophrenia is that it is a diagnosis, that is a clinical label, applied by some people to others.”[24] The essentially social process which results ultimately in the fixing of this label to one person is the underlying theme of three books and a good many articles by Dr. Laing and his colleagues. I shall try to outline their account of this process subsequently, but an idea of their truly radical conclusions can be given here:
“We do not use the term ‘schizophrenia’ to denote any identifiable condition which we believe exists ‘in’ one person.”[25]
“I do not myself believe that there is any such ‘condition’ as schizophrenia. …”[26]
“Schizophrenia is not a disease in one person but rather a crazy“Schizophrenia, if it means anything, is a more or less characteristic mode of disturbed group behaviour. There are no schizophrenics.”[28]
“Over the last two decades there has been a growing dissatisfaction with any theory or study of the individual which artificially isolates him from the context of his life, interpersonal and social.”
Sartre holds that all groups are structured against an awareness of a “spectator”. This “spectator” may be an individual—
The British existentialists make use of two words, series and nexus, in differentiating between kinds of group—
Praxis and process are both terms used by Sartre. Basically, praxis is what is done by someone: “deeds done by doers”, “the acts of an individual or group”; whilst process refers to “what just happens”, activity not intended by anyone and of which no one person in a group may be aware.
The position of the person within the group will affect his idea of himself—
Dr. Laing’s second book The Self and Others deals with the way in which a person is affected by his situation in a “nexus” of others, in particular within the family. “The others either can contribute to the person’s self-fulfilment, or they can be a potent factor in his losing himself (alienation) even to the point of madness.” He asserts his belief that “fantasy is a mode of experience” and that relationships on a fantasy level are “as basic to all human relatedness as the interactions that most people most of the time are more aware of.”
What happens in the families of “schizophrenics”? It is important to emphasise that it is not the thesis of these workers that the family rather than the individual is “ill”. A group is not an organism—- “The patient was a good, normal, healthy child; until she gradually began
- “to be bad, to do or say things that caused great distress, and which were on the whole ‘put down’ to naughtiness or badness, until
- “this went beyond all tolerable limits so that she could only be regarded as completely mad.”
What was seen by the mother as her daughter’s “good” period, in infancy and early childhood, she described with such remarks as “she gave no trouble”, “she always did what she was told”. Laing comments that what to the mother were signs of goodness, were signs that the child had never been permitted to become “existentially alive”—
In Sanity, Madness and the Family (the first volume of an uncompleted study) Drs. Laing and Esterson present extracts from interviews with members of 11 families, all of which contained daughters diagnosed as “schizophrenic”. In the Introduction to this book the authors write “… we believe that we show that the experience and behaviour of schizophrenics is much more socially intelligible than has come to be supposed by most psychiatrists … we believe that the shift of point of view that these descriptions both embody and demand has an historical significance no less radical than the shift from a demonological to a clinical viewpoint 300 years ago.” Behaviour which is eventually interpreted by the family as a sign of madness is, they argue, the outward expression of a desperate attempt on the part of the “mad one” to “make sense of a senseless situation”—
These writers claim, and I think demonstrate, that armed with a knowledge of the patient’s existential situation, it is possible to make sense of what “psychiatrists still by and large regard as nonsense”. For example, Julie, the patient in “The Ghost of the Weed Garden” referred to herself whilst in her “psychotic” state as “Mrs. Taylor” and as a “tolled bell”. Dr. Laing interprets her chosen title “Mrs. Taylor” as expressing the feelings: “I’m tailor made; I’m a tailored maid; I was made, fed, clothed and tailored” and a “tolled bell” is also “the told belle” “the girl who always did what she was told”. The schizophrenic’s “delusions” of persecution are real expressions of reaction in response to real persecution and are existentially true; that is to say they are “literally true statements within the terms of reference of the individual who makes them.”††
The person is now launched on a “career” as a mental patient. He is confirmed in this role by society’s agents the psychiatrists, in collusion with the patient’s family, and by process of betrayal and degradation[34] becomes an inmate of a mental hospital, which institution embodies “a social structure which in many respects reduplicates the maddening peculiarities of the patient’s family … he finds psychiatrists, administrators, nurses who are his veritable parents, brothers, sisters, who play an interpersonal game which only too often resembles in the intricacies of its rules the game he failed in at home.”[35]
The existential analysts have asserted that a great deal of what passes for treatment in mental institutions is violence. Perhaps we can now begin to see what is meant by this. David Cooper in his article in Views, No. 8 quotes Sartre’s definition of violence: “The corrosive
THEORIES IN PRACTICE: “THE ANTI-HOSPITAL”
In his pamphlet Youth for Freedom (1951) Tony Gibson wrote to the effect that the chief value of Summerhill to the community lay in its having taken the general concept of what a school should be and turned it on its head. Dr. David Cooper’s unit in a large mental hospital “just north-west of London” has done very much the same thing to the general concept of the asylum. To maintain the educational parallel, Dr. Cooper’s experiment (judging from his account of it in New Society[37] also has great relevance for those who would wish to attack the violence implicit in the customary methods of social organisation in schools.
The unit—
The programme during the first year was highly structured, with daily meetings of the whole staff-patient group, separate and regular staff meetings, occupational therapy and organised recreational activity. No “physical” treatments were used except for the occasional dose of mild tranquilliser, and there was no individual psycho-therapy; there were however regular “interviews” between therapist and patient and therapist and patient with various members of his family. After about a year, the staff became dissatisfied with the rigidities of the system and changes in the direction of greater fluidity were felt to be appropriate.
Dr. Cooper writes of two areas in which the consequent “destructuring” had remarkable effects—
The workers in the unit were faced with conflicting pressures—
The position of the experimental ward inside the framework of the large hospital prompted the growth of fantastic and distorted attitudes towards the unit in the minds of senior staff members working outside it; this indicated the deep challenge which the new approach made to their more traditional concepts. For example an incident one night, in which an hysterical girl patient was helped back to her ward by a male friend was “processed” by the communications system until in its final form, it had become a case of attempted sexual assault.
An Assessment of the success of the “anti-hospital” in terms of “results” (usually measured in such cases by the incidence of re-admission) would not be any more meaningful than a judgement on Summerhill based simply on the pupil’s success rate in public examinations. The criterion of re-admission rates is also inadequate in that staff encouraged patients to return after discharge if they felt that a return to the unit would be of value to them. Nevertheless, even by this standard the “anti-hospital” results compare favourably with those achieved by more widely accepted methods— As a postscript to the foregoing, I can deal only sketchily with an intriguing aspect of the work of the British existentialists—
CRITICISM AND CONCLUSIONS
The only extended criticism known to me of the work and ideas of these British psychiatrists is an article by B. A. Farrell called “The Logic of Existential Analysis” which appeared in New Society (1.10.65). This writer argues that the existentialists have dismissed orthodox views on the causes and treatment of schizophrenia on inadequate grounds and also make logically unwarrantable deductions from their research into families of schizophrenics. Referring to the claim of Laing and Esterson that they have made the “symptoms” of schizophrenia intelligible, he makes the point that even if they are successful in doing this, making the symptoms intelligible is not the same thing as establishing truth for their hypothesis. Farrell comments that “this would be a trivial point to make” if we had other grounds for believing that the narratives were true. In relation to their suggestions for treatment he asks for evidence that units of the “anti-hospital” type produce results “as good as, or better than, the traditional methods”. In conclusion he advises them that some of the opposition to their work might not have been so vehement had they avoided “abusive” and “intemperate” language in their references to the Establishment; and also that “they would help themselves if they could avoid giving the impression that they had fallen in love with their schizophrenic patients. …”
Correspondents in subsequent issues suggested some answers to these criticisms. Commenting on Mr. Farrell’s remark on the lack of supportive evidence, Dr. John Bowlby wrote: “Although Dr. Laing’s is the only psychiatric group in this country publishing material of its sort, in the United States there are several. The two best known are the group at the National Institute of Mental Health … and the one at Palo Alto. … Each of these research groups has used methods and reported findings essentially similar to those of Dr. Laing. Some of their most recent reports … are of projects that at critical points in the procedure are ‘blind’ in just the way that Mr. Farrell rightly requests. In addition to a number of findings derived from quite other methods are supportive. … There is thus substantial evidence derived from more than one method in support of the Laing type of hypothesis. … When compared with evidence advanced to support other types of hypothesis, it is not unimpressive. On the one hand it is far more substantial than any yet offered in support of psycho-analytic theories, whether traditional or Kleinian, and, on the other, more consistent than that supporting a genetic-biochemical type of theory” (my italics).[41]
I have already made some reference to the “results”, in terms of re-admissions, of the “anti-hospital” which were published in the Mr. Farrell’s final charge is valuable in that it draws attention to the basis of the method of existential analysis as described and practised by Dr. Laing and his colleagues. I do not think that Dr. Laing would wish to deny that “love” is involved in his attitude towards his patients and their predicament. In The Divided Self he writes of the act of empathy—
As I hope I have succeeded in indicating in this article, the work of Drs. Laing, Cooper and Esterson constitutes far more than just another theory of what causes “schizophrenia”; a correspondent in New Society characterised it as “an exploration of the necessary conditions for a fully human relationship”.[44]
Dr. Laing has suggested that the reason why exploration of the “inner” world of the self is invalidated by society as “madness” is that such experience is subversive. “And it is subversive because it is real.”[45] Deified destructive illusions—
I hope that, as Dr. Laing has hinted, their future work will involve and imply further criticism in depth, or our society; if this is the case it will have direct relevance for contemporary anarchism (notwithstanding the association of these writers with a form of Marxism). In conclusion, I would risk the statement that the body of work they have so far produced—
** An article in The Observer (4.9.66) announced the formation of “Project 70”—
*** This may be an allusion to a case which was receiving some publicity at that time. Zenya Belov, a student, was confined in a Russian mental institution around September, 1965—
† References to a letter from Brenda Jordan in Peace News (17.6.66).
†† See also Laing’s interpretation of the statements of a schizophrenic from the original account in Kraepelin’s Lectures on Clinical Psychiatry, 1905 (pp. 29-31 The Divided Self). Laing writes: “What does this patient seem to be doing? Surely he is carrying on a dialogue between his own parodied version of Kraepelin, and his own defiant rebelling self. ‘You want to know that too? I tell you who is being measured and is measured and shall be measured. I know all that, and I could tell you, but I do not want to’.” Laing comments: “This seems to be plain enough talk.”
††† Since this was written an article has appeared. “Schizophrenia as a way of life”, by Ruth Abel (Guardian, 4.10.66), describing a “fully autonomous unit” for “schizophrenics” established by Drs. Laing, Esterson and Cooper at Kingsley Hall in London. This project is financed by The Philadelphia Association and it seems that two new centres have been opened during the last few months in North London, and it is hoped that these are only the first of “a chain of communities”.
David Cooper, “Sartre on Genet”, New Left Review, No. 25.
R. D. Laing, The Politics of Experience and the Bird of Paradise, Penguin Books, Autumn, 1966.
R. D. Laing, H. Phillipson, A. R. Lee, Interpersonal Perception: A Theory and a Method, London, Tavistock, 1966.
T. S. Szasz, The Myth of Mental Illness, London, Seeker and Warburg, 1962.
Carl R. Rogers, On Becoming a Person, London, Constable & Co., 1961.
<references>
- ↑ Robert G. Olson, An Introduction to Existentialism, New York, Dover Publications, 1962, p. 52.
- ↑ ibid., p. 105 (a reference to an episode in Being and Nothingness, p. 495).
- ↑ J.-P. Sartre, Situations III, Paris, Gallimard, 1949 (quoted by Olson, p. 121).
- ↑ Olson, op. cit., p. 119.
- ↑ J.-P. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, London, Methuen, 1956, pp. 461-2.
- ↑ ibid., pp. 471-75 (quoted by Olson, p. 121).
- ↑ The first part of R. D. Laing’s The Self and Others is a lucid argument against the basic concepts of traditional psycho-
analysis. - ↑ “Massacre of the Innocents”, Peace News, 22nd January, 1965.
- ↑ BBC “Panorama” on “Mental Health”, 6th June, 1966.
- ↑ David Cooper, “The Anti-Hospital: An Experiment in Psychiatry”, New Society, 11th March, 1965.
- ↑ David Cooper, “Violence in Psychiatry”, Views, No. 8, Summer, 1965.
- ↑ ibid.
- ↑ Part of a letter by Pierre-Joseph Brie, “Insanity and the Egg”, Peace News, 1st July, 1966.
- ↑ T. S. Szasz, “Politics and Mental Health”, American Journal of Psychiatry, No. 115 (1958) (quoted by Erving Goffman in Asylums, p. 509).
- ↑ Erving Goffman, <span data-html="true" class="plainlinks" title="Wikipedia: Asylums—
Essays on the Social Situation of Mental Patients and Other Inmates">Asylums— Essays on the Social Situation of Mental Patients and Other Inmates, New York, Anchor Books, 1961, pp. 363-4. - ↑ ibid., p. 354.
- ↑ ibid., p. 135.
- ↑ ibid., p. 380.
- ↑ For a reconstruction of a psychiatric interrogation see “The Case Conference”, Views, No. 11, Summer, 1966. <span data-html="true" class="plainlinks" title="Wikipedia: Elias Canetti<!-- 'Elia Canetti' in original -->">Elias Canetti<!-- 'Elia Canetti' in original --> has written that “questioning is a forcible intrusion. When used as an instrument of power, it is like a knife cutting into the flesh of the victim. … The most blatant tyranny is the one that asks the most questions” (Crowds and Power, Gollancz, 1962).
- ↑ A sentence of Dr. Joshua Dierer’s, speaking at the World Federation of Mental Health, 1960 (quoted by Colin Ward in “Where The Shoe Pinches”, anarchy 4).
- ↑ Goffman, op. cit., p. 384.
- ↑ An estimate made by the Swiss psychiatrist E. Bleuler, quoted by David Cooper in “The Anti-Hospital”.
- ↑ P. Rube, “Healing Process in Schizophrenia”, Journal of Nervous and Mental Diseases, 1948 (quoted by John Linsie in “Schizophrenia: A Social Disease”, anarchy 24).
- ↑ R. D. Laing, “What is Schizophrenia?”, New Left Review, No. 28.
- ↑ R. D. Laing and A. Esterson, Sanity, Madness and the Family, London, Tavistock, 1964.
- ↑ R. D. Laing, “What is Schizophrenia?”, op. cit.
- ↑ David Cooper, “The Anti-Hospital”, op. cit.
- ↑ David Cooper, Violence in Psychiatry, Views, No. 8.
- ↑ R. D. Laing, “Us and Them”, Views, No. 11.
- ↑ R. D. Laing and A. Esterson, op. cit.
- ↑ R. D. Laing, “Us and Them”, op. cit.
- ↑ David Cooper, “Two Types of Rationality”, New Left Review, No. 29.
- ↑ op. cit., p. 155.
- ↑ Erving Goffman in Asylums makes use of the term “career” to denote “the social strand” of a person’s life inaugurated at the moment of his definition as a mental patient; “betrayal funnel” to describe the circuit of figures (relatives, psychiatrists, etc.) whose interactions end with the patient’s confinement in the 374asylum, and “degradation ceremonial” for the psychiatric examination preceding the patient’s admission.
- ↑ David Cooper, “Violence in Psychiatry”, op. cit.
- ↑ ibid.
- ↑ New Society, 11th March, 1965.
- ↑ British Medical Journal, No. 5476, p. 1462.
- ↑ R. D. Laing, “What is Schizophrenia?”, op. cit.
- ↑ ibid.
- ↑ Extract from letter in New Society, 4th November, 1965.
- ↑ R. D. Laing, The Divided Self—
An Existential Study in Sanity and Madness, London, Tavistock, 1960 (Pelican Books, 1965). - ↑ ibid., p. 165.
- ↑ A phrase from a letter by J. D. Ingleby (Applied Psychology Research Unit, Cambridge), New Society, 28th October, 1965.
- ↑ “A Ten Day Voyage”, Views, No. 8.
- ↑ “Us and Them”, op. cit.
- ↑ “Freud Revisited”—
a review of Herbert Marcuse’s Eros and Civilization, New Left Review, No. 20.